Towards a philosophy of Buddhist religion

by Frank J. Hoffman

Asian Philosophy

Vol. 1 No. 1 1991

Pp.21-28

Copyright by Asian Philosophy


There are signs of a growing awareness that philosophy of religion is not equivalent to the philosophy of (Christian) religion [11. Although it remains logically possible to do philosophy of religion as if Christianity were the only religion, the purpose of this paper is to argue for a way of doing philosophy of religion so as to take into account religions other than Christianity, in this case Buddhism. In what follows I outline the main features of the proposed approach against the background of some ideas about method and as an alternative to the contemporary approaches of Steven Collins and Don Cupitt in humanities and theology respectively. P. T. Raju, in his assessment of 'Radhakrishnan's influence on Indian Thought', distinguishes three types of comparative philosophy as follows [2]: (1) 'the first is interested in treating a system, school, or tradition as a function of its environment' (2) 'the second treats a concept as a function of a system' (3) the third has 'the main purpose of co-ordinating and synthesizing the basic values of life' of india and the West. This third type is Radhakrishnan's and the second that of Masson-Ourse1 according to Raju. (The first, I think, is the approach of Watsuji Tetsuro in Climate: A Philosophical Study [2a].) Although my work, Rationality and Mind in Early Buddhism, does not fit neatly into any of these three categories, insofar as it is a conceptual map of part of the early Buddhist terrain with concepts of mind located within it, the second approach comes nearest [3]. My present concern is to extend (2), the contextual approach to comparative philosophy mentioned by Raju above, to the philosophy of religion. Philosophy of religion is here seen as a branch of philosophy which focuses on religion. What shape would a philosophy of Buddhist religion take? What advantages are there to such an approach? In this paper I would like to answer these questions. One advantage to undertaking to construct a philosophy of Buddhist religion is that doing so does justice to both philosophical and religious interests. It does so by approaching Buddhist religious thought from the perspective of philosophy of religion, in the same spirit in which Christian thought and religion has been, and continues to be, approached. This is, on the one hand to make a conceptual map of the terrain; on the other hand, to identify areas of adjustment and maladjustment of concepts within the system. But rather than just treating a concept as a function of a system, discrepancies may be pointed out, so that the approach is not only descriptive but also critical and philosophical. The result is not supposed to be some static monumental production. For both in research and in teaching philosophy of Buddhist religion, the emphasis should be on philosophy as a process of inquiry rather than mainly on philosophy as a doctrinal product. In choosing the word 'thought' we do justice to the intellectual side of Buddhism without making it unduly intellectualistic. As Geroge Chatalian indicates, Buddhism has been approached both as a philosophy and as a religion, often without an articulated concept of either one being presented [4]. His article is a worthwhile reminder that attention should be given to the question of whether it is preferable to treat Buddhism as a philosophy or as a religion and for what reasons. I am less than sanguine about Chatalian's insistence that it is either 'correct or incorrect' to say that Buddhism is philosophy or that it is religion. He thinks that this is a straightforward matter of empirical fact, such as (in his example) whether cyanide is poison or food [5]. However, Buddhism may be philosophy under one description and religion under another description, so that the ambiguity of the expression 'Buddhist thought' may be useful to cover both possibilities. My view of the Buddhism of the Suttapitaka is that these are religious texts which have philosophical implications. Chatalian's view puts him in the odd position of asserting that Buddhism is philosophy, while denying that it has any of the traditional parts of philosophy (logic, metaphysics, and epistemology are explicitly excluded). The antidote to the confusion of Buddhist philosophy without branches is to see it as a religion with philosophical implications. Contra Chatalian this sort of view is not mainly a Western one, for Radhakrishnan (to take a salient example) often refers to the need for religion and discusses Buddhism as such. It is to Radhakrishnan's view that I now turn. In characterising 'philosophy of religion', Radhakrishnan writes: "Philosophy of religion is religion come to an understanding of itself" [6]. He also clearly recognises that "while religion implies a metaphysical view of the universe, it is not to be confused with philosophy" [7]. I think that philosophy of religion (and eo ipso philosophy of Buddhist religion) is basically a conceptual inquiry. It may be faith achieving understanding of itself as Radhakrishnan says, but it is not necessarily religious. 'Philosophy of religion' is not equivalent to 'religious philosophy'. Philosophers are not necessarily sages, nor do they have the direct hotline to the Truth typically claimed by sages. For the present writer, only a careful selection of Radhakrishnan's views is acceptable. In general, as F. S.C. Northrop notes, Radhakrishnan's world philosophical synthesis is much more difficult than his analysis indicates and requires for its solution a method different from the one derived from the Oriental type of knowledge and intuitive concept of the spiritual which he uses. [8] There is one sort of theology or religious philosophy which obtains inspiration from Buddhism that must be clearly distinguished from the Philosophy of Buddhist Religion as I understand it. It is currently best exemplified in the very interesting work of Don Cupitt, Dean of Emmanuel College Cambridge. Anyone with a sympathetic interest in Asian thought and culture will appreciate Professor Cupitt's theological approach, since it is tangential to Eastern ways of thinking on several points. However, his voice speaks more directly to contemporary Christians qua Christians than to contemporary philosophers qua philosophers. Indeed, Cupitt concedes much more to relativism than philosophers tend to do, and he does not put much stock in philosophical argument as such. The current of intellectual history and our present situation are of much greater interest to Cupitt. But he fathoms this current as tending towards a 'Christian spirituality' in the conclusion of The Sea of Faith: And why choose one form of religious life rather than another? Kierkegaard has given the answer, and shown the form a modern apologetic must take. His method is to expound each particular form of life from within, like a novelist. He does not need to test it against any supposed metaphysical realities external to it. It is sufficient to explore its values, its inner logic, and the life-possibilities that it opens up. By this method we may be able to show purely from within that particular way of life eventually runs into difficulties that can be solved only by making a transition to another one (this is all that is meant by Kierkegaard's allegedly irrational 'leap of faith'). I for one believe that if in this way we were to explore Nietzchean humanism and Buddhism we might be able to show that each has its limits and both are fulfilled in a Christian spirituality that can unite the radical humanism of the one with the high spiritual attainment of the other. [9] Showing this is a tall order and an interesting programme. As I understand the job of philosophy of religion, however, it is not to do apologetics. Instead, religion must be understood 'warts and all', and a philosophy of Buddhist religion would point out both 'the beauty points' as well as the 'warts' of Buddhism. It is the disinterested pursuit of truth (rather than apologetics) that marks the character of the approach favoured. Another way in which Cupitt's approach is fundamentally different from my own is that Cupirt is sceptical of the value of philosophy. In Taking Leave of God, for instance, he claims: Philosophy is done on the basis of a noble lie, a necessary fiction, namely the belief that a thesis can be expressed unambiguously and evaluated conclusively. [10] This passage occurs in the context of Cupitt's argument against the view that all of the arguments for the existence of God are invalid and that the existence of God cannot be proved. He argues that: You could only say such a thing if the arguments could be stated in definitive forms, and in those forms be conclusively shown to be valid or invalid. Philosophers like to pretend they can achieve this quasi-mathematical precision, but history suggests the opposite. [11] The main difficulty with this argument is one of self-reference: if it is false that "a thesis can be expressed unambiguously and evaluated conclusively", then there is no ground on which Cupitt can express his own thesis and show conclusively that it is so. Hence Cupitt's conclusion, "so the history of the debate does not entitle us to conclude with certainty that God's existence is either provable or unprovable", itself cannot be known with certainty. Cupirt departs company with philosophers at precisely the interesting point at which doing philosophy becomes risky (and not simply business). It is, I think, an unavoidable occupational hazard of philosophers that they take positions on issues. It is not necessary in so doing to do so arrogantly, as Griffiths explains: Where it seems appropriate I shall not hesitate to offer critical assessments of both the arguments presented in those [Indian Buddhist] traditions and of the truth of the premises involved therein. I undertake this enterprise with the humility appropriate to all philosophical enterprises -- the knowledge, among other things, that I am likely to be frequently wrong. But I reject that humility which, all too often in those Western academic circles where the study of Buddhist thought is carried on, refuses to take its material with philosophical seriousness. [12] In contrast to Cupitt's de-emphasis of philosophical reasoning, Griffiths' approach is preferable, since it combines an awareness of philosophy's limits with perseverance in philosophical argument. Griffiths also recognises the importance of clarifying one's metapractice [12a]. Yet Cupitt is an important contemporary theologian and bold thinker. One strand of his belief is a conscious ecumenicism, marked by the conviction that Christian-Buddhist synthesis is viable. Although there is an extremely cosmopolitan air evident in his writing, such that he tends to breeze past views actually held by religious conservatives with statements to the effect that no one any longer believes such-and-such, it is not this tendency to conflate the believable with the believed that is intriguing, rather it is the ecumenical, and specifically pro-Buddhist, aspect of his presentation. Cupitt states in the Preface to Taking Leave of God: of the great world faiths, Buddhism comes closest to what I have in mind. [13] He envisages a view with Buddhist form and Christian content. Cupitt writes: equation of religiosity with dependency (typical of the Enlightenment and of Freud) is sufficiently refuted by the mention of Buddhism, which has no trace of dependency. [14] Cupitt considers Buddhism to involve nirvana, meditation, and self-reliance in contrast to the heaven, prayer, and dependency in Christianity. He is pessimistic about the ability of Christianity to go it alone, and argues for a 'Christian Buddhism' which does not make "unnecessary and unprovable doctrinal claims". In this he writes as if all of Buddhism were Zen, and ignores the important role of doctrinal claims in the Buddhist tradition. Although self-reliance ('Be an island or lamp for yourself") is an important Buddhist idea, so is faith or confidence (saddha). Even in early Indian Buddhism initial faith, practical faith on the path, and realised faith as a mark of the Tathagata are emphasised numerous times throughout the Nikayas, and Cupitt appears to be unaware of this. There is also the idea of 'taking refuge' in the Buddha, doctrine, and monastic order (the 'three refuges' or tisarana). Both saddha and the tisarana indicate that Cupitt's contrast between dependency in Christianity and self-reliance in Buddhism is overstated. In Mahayana sects which emphasise that 'other power' is necessary for salvation, Cupitt's contrast falls down most markedly. In addition, there are major differences between sects of Buddhism and Cupitt does not make clear with which sect his own views are supposed to be compatible. Consequently a critic may well wonder whether it is Buddhism or Cupitt's none-too-specific and somewhat idealised view of Buddhism that offers an avenue to dialogue. Indeed religious conservatives may say that Cupitt's Buddhism, or 'Christian Buddhism' is virtually unrecognisable as either Buddhism or as Christianity. The way in which it arguably falls between the stools is in reference to the concept of God. How can 'Christian Buddhism' be possible without contradiction? Can one retain the concept of God, even a radically reinterpreted one, in any form of atheistic Buddhism? Unworried by such concerns, Cupitt asserts that God is not "a distinct person", but "the religious requirement personified" [15]. There is no god but the religious requirement: "Become Spirit!" [16]. That it is neither orthodox Buddhism nor orthodox Christianity is not, I think, the main problem. It is that whether and how it is possible to "become Spirit" is left intolerably vague. His three converging themes: the internalisation of meaning and value, the autonomy of the human subject, and the indwelling of God in the believer, sound remarkably like popular psychology of the self-realisation variety [ 17]. And in place of the philosophical and theological argument that one might expect to find against, for example, understanding God as a being, one finds scepticism of philosophical argument [ 18], and a tendency to give 'sociological' answers to philosophical problems. My own view is that there is a need for philosophical attention to the conceptual problems of particular religions. History of religions, textual studies, and the approach to religion via sociology, anthropology, and psychology all have their place. But none of these can take the place of philosophical attention to religions. In particular, without a philosophy of Buddhist religion we do not respect the claims of Buddhist thought deeply enough to either agree or disagree with them. Without a philosophical approach, Buddhism could be viewed as a mere curiosity, a museum piece of antiquarian interest alone. What is salutary in both Griffiths's and Cupitt's approaches is the attempt to come to terms with Buddhism in its philosophical and religious depth respectively. But as we have seen, Cupitt's approach denies philosophical development its full flowering. In this respect it resembles Steven Collins' work, Selfless Persons. On the positive side, Steven Collins has written one of the most interesting and worthwhile books on Buddhism to appear in recent years. It shows the ability to do close reading of Pall texts and yet the breadth of vision to see Buddhism in cultural terms. A fresh approach is provided by his emphasis on the 'imagery' in Buddhist thought, such as house imagery, vegetation imagery, and river imagery. The work is well-organised and leads the reader through four parts concerning the cultural and social setting of Buddhist thought, the doctrine of no-self, personality and rebirth, and continuity. One of the work's strong points is the way in which standard distinctions are set forth in a clear manner, e.g. that between transmigration and rebirth as two sorts of reincarnation views [19], and the distinction between nibbana in the individual's lifetime and nibbana at the death of the enlightened saint (saupadisesa and anupddisesa) [20]. It is, without doubt, an important contribution to Buddhist studies. But to accept Collins' approach in Selfless Persons would be to foreclose significant options in the study of Buddhism. This can be seen by assembling remarks made throughout the text on method. Early on the reader is informed that the method used will not be the Wittgensteinian philosophical one of seeking "immunity from external historical or sociological criticism and comparison", but rather that of placing oneself in a Buddhist world "experiencing Buddhist categories" [21]. The work is offered as "an essay in the history of ideas", which is both scholarly and philosophical: "my main interest is philosophical" [22]. Yet when addressing the main doctrine of the study, that of anatta by focusing on such translated terms as 'self', 'person', 'death', 'rebirth', 'release', and 'enlightenment', Collins regards it as mistaken to take the task as "simply to make a judgment of our own on the relations, logical or otherwise, between these concepts, and on the 'ultimate reality' to which they are taken to refer" [23]. Instead the task of the scholar is to investigate "by any and every academic discipline which proves necessary", the works in which the beliefs and doctrines, categories and functions of Buddhism appear. Collins sees himself as a scholar writing for a broad audience of philosophers and intellectual historians [24]. Later it turns out that "what scholarship can do is two-fold": to explicate the values and presuppositions of Indian thought at the time of the Buddha that enable one to understand his soteriological strategy of anatta; to examine how it was and can be applied to the life of the Buddhist monk. Now some questions may be raised about Collins' method. Is the main interest of a work philosophical when it side-steps difficult questions of the relations between concepts, eschewing such concerns in favour of a purely descriptive map-making project of the Buddhist terrain? [25] Only if philosophy is perversely taken to be equivalent with intellectual history is Collins' main interest 'philosophical'. Although seemingly open to the employment of philosophical method or any other disciplinary perspective that would elucidate Buddhism, the work is actually not philosophical in any other way than the extremely attenuated way 'history of philosophy' is 'philosophical' [26]. In effect the restriction upon 'what scholarship can do' rules out any strictly philosophical concerns over the logical compatibility or incompatibility of concepts or judgments inP>Collins forecloses inquiry at precisely the interesting point -- that of the logical relations between ideas in Buddhism -- in favour of explanations in terms of social forces, e.g. "What turned this statistically unusual type of feeling into the commonly accepted ultimate religious goal in India was the particular social position and prestige of the world-renouncer and his quest" [27]. Eschewing philosophical questions may be from some disciplinary perspectives perfectly legitimate, but one cannot consistently do so in the same work which claims that one's main concern is philosophical. In contrast to the approaches of Collins and Cupirt, the method of a philosophy of Buddhist religion begins to take shape. A philosophy of Buddhist religion should: (a) take its material with philosophical seriousness: be critical and evaluative; (b) raise problems against the background of the Buddhist texts themselves: be textually based; (c) treat Buddhism as a religion with philosophical implications (i.e. as 'Buddhist thought'); (d) take a comparative approach when necessary to illuminate a specific problem-the comparative approach may relate ideas of Eastern or Western thinkers in both philosophy and religion; (e) analyse conceptual problems rather than put forth religious beliefs. To modify a metaphor from Ninian Smart, if the house of religion has many rooms, then I suggest that one be reserved for the Philosophy of Buddhist Religion [28]. It can occupy the penultimate floor in a slightly expanded and hence remodelled version of Smart's house of religion. My remodelled house includes the improvements of giving philosophy of religion a clear place within the study of religion and a pluralistic role. (For any particular religion, X, there could be constructed a 'philosophy of X religion'.) According to Smart's view, the 'philosophy of worldviews' occupies the top floor of the house of religion, which has as its middle floor the comparative and historical analysis of religions and ideologies, and as a ground floor the phenomenology not just of religious experience and action but of the symbolic life of a man as a whole. [29] In Religion and the Western Mind Smart explains that the term 'worldview' covers both traditional religious systems of belief and practice as well as secular systems of a similar nature [30]. My proposal for a philosophy of Buddhist religion is not in conflict with Smart's philosophy of worldviews, but can be articulated as a modification of the same picture of a 'house of religion' which is pluralistic enough to include several methodologies within its walls. Constructing a philosophy of Buddhist religion is one job among many in the field of religious studies; it is one in which the tools of the philosophical trade are essential. Although it is a job which will not appeal to everyone, not even to all philosophers, that fact does not minimise its importance as a creative and critical task of the human spirit. NOTES [1] In William Wainwright, Philosophy of Religion (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1988), there are several references to Buddhism, and in John Hick, Philosophy of Religion 3rd edition (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1983), ch. 8 concerns conflicting truth claims of different religions while ch. 10 focuses on karma and reincarnation. These contemporary attempts to take religions other than Christianity into account in the writing of general textbooks reveal a trend away from the view according to which philosophy of religion is identical to philosophy of Christian religion. [2] RAJU, P. T. 'Radhakrishnan's Influence on Indian Thought', in: Paul A. Schilpp (Ed.), The Philosophy of Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan (New York: Tudor Publishing, 1952), pp. 526-528. [2a] WATSUJI, TETSURO Climate: a philosophical study (New York: Greenwood Press, 1988). [3] HOFFMAN, FRANK J. Rationality and Mind in Early Buddhism (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987), p. 3. [4] CHATALIAN, GEORGE (1983) 'Early Indian Buddhism and the Nature of Philosophy: a philosophical investigation', in: Journal of Indian Philosophy, 11(3), p. 209. [5] CHATALlAN, ibid., pp. 212-213. [6] RADHAKRISHNAN, SARVEPALLI, An Idealist View of Life (London: Allen & Unwin, 1932), p. 84. [7] RADHAKRISHNAN, op. cit., p. 88. [8] NORTHROP, F. S.C. 'Radhakrishnan's Conception of the Relation Between Eastern and Western Cultural Values', in: SCHILPP, op. cit., p. 658. [9] CUPITT, DON The Sea of Faith (London: BBC Publications, 1984), pp. 272-273. [10] CUPITT, DON Taking Leave of God (New York: Crossroad, 1980), p. 32. [11] CUPITT, ibid., p. 32. [12] GRIFFITHS, PAUL J. On Being Mindless (Illinois: Open Court, 1986), p. xix. [12a] GRIFFITHS, PAUL. J. 'Denaturalizing Discourse: Abhidarnikas, Propositionalists and the Comparative Philosophy of Religion', in: Frank Reynolds & David Tracy (Eds) Myth and Philosophy (New York: Suny Press, 1990), p. 81. [13] CUPITT, ibid., p. xii. [14] Ibid., p. 2. [15] Ibid., p. 85. [16] Ibid., p. 91. [17] Ibid., p. 5. [18] Ibid., p. 32. [19] COLLINS, STEVEN Selfless Persons (Cambridge: C.U.P., 1982), p. 5. [20] Ibid., p. 83. [21] Ibid., p. 3. [22] Ibid., p. 1. [23] Ibid., p. 12. [24] Ibid., p. 26. [25] Ibid., pp. 1, 12. [26] Ibid., p. 12. [27] Ibid., p. 63. [28] SMART, NINIAN 'The Philosophy of Worldviews: the Philosophy of Religion Transformed', in: DON WEIBE (Ed.) Concept and Empathy (New York: New York University Press, 1986), p. 85. It is worth noticing that some time ago in his interview, 'Conversation with Ninian Smart', in: BRYAN MAGEE (Ed.) Modern British Philosophy (London: Secker & Warburg, 1971), Smart indicated that one direction in which philosophy of religion might move is toward the social sciences, and was uncertain as to whether it could have any other future (p. 175). If the methodology outlined in this paper is viable, however, the philosophy of religion can have a future in application to the texts of religious traditions such as Buddhism and need not be absorbed either by phenomenology or by the social sciences. [29] SMART, NINIAN (1986) 'The Philosophy of Worldviews: the Philosophy of Religion Transformed', in: Dos WEIBE (Ed.) Concept and Empathy (New York: New York University Press), p. 85. [30] SMART, NINIAN (1987) Religion and the Western Mind (New York: State University of New York Press), pp. 10-11.