The Buddha and Wittgenstein: A brief philosophical exegesis

by A.D.P. Kalansuriya

Asian Philosophy

Vol. 3 No. 2 1993

Pp103-112

Copyright by Carfax Publishing Company


ABSTRACT An attempt is made to analyse the key notions in the Buddha's Dhamma--'truth', 'knowledge', 'emancipation'--by way of the philosophical techniques of the later Wittgenstein. The analysis hence is both comparative and noncomparative. It is comparative because two thought processes from two different traditions are brought together. And it is noncomparative since it brings into focus a philosophical exegesis as against a comparative exposition. In the process not only are philosophical errors in comparative exposition made explicit in our thesis but it also offers a genuine basis for modern Buddhist philosophy. (1) Introduction A philosopher of Buddhism is not tied by the kinds of restrictions that limit a Christian or a Hindu philosopher. The Buddha himself encouraged his followers to analyse, exposit and test his teaching in the light of contemporary views, techniques and tools. The followers of the Buddha are by no means bound to be faithful to the doctrine, and philosophical exegesis, exposition and clarification of notions are deemed entirely laudable. But, then, is it not the case that Western philosophical techniques when applied, remain misapplied and wasted? Much scepticism can spring up from such a question, and, therefore, serious study of Buddhism by way of Western philosophical techniques may be conceived as both misleading and superficial. We propose, however, that there is a scholarly desire, namely, to apply a series of philosophical techniques to Buddhism to monitor the possible consequences. Treading this conceptual path, we shall apply the later Wittgensteinean philosophical techniques to the Buddha-Dhamma. But why Wittgensteinean philosophical techniques? There are two reasons. First, it is now widely thought that Wittgenstein is one of the most important philosophers of our century. Second, Wittgenstein avoids commonplace comparative thinking involving the Buddha-Dhamma and philosophy. Characteristic of this comparative thinking is an unusual enthusiasm for a modern Buddhism, for men and women of modern cultural patterns, which uncritically commits itself to Western empiricism, positivism and scientific philosophies. This kind of discourse uproots the Buddha-Dhamma--the message of the Buddha--from the life to which it naturally belongs, in which it is used, and in which it has meaning and drive. These comparative expositions have consequently bred distortions--the results being fallacies and philosophical errors. A few passages from well known works are cited below. (2) Some examples The Dynamic Psychology of Early Buddhism, Johansson, R. E. A., Curzon Press, Oxford, 1979, pp. 144-5 It is a well known fact that, according to Buddhism, all living beings are reborn in accordance with their activities, kamma. This seems like a metaphysical doctrine outside the domain of psychology; and, therefore, of no interest in this treatise. But, to the Buddha, it was a verifiable perceptual fact. Actually, it is said that anybody can, by concentrating his mind, recollect at least one previous life (tathdnpam cetosamadhim phusati yatha samahite citte tam pubbenivasanussatti, D.III.32). It was considered a normal 'fruit of life as a recluse' (smanapala) to be able to recall many, even a hundred thousand previous lives after reaching certain levels of samadhi (D.I.81). It might, therefore, be relevant to ask whether any psychological factors are at work in the process of rebirth. The Dancing Wu Li Masters, Zukav, Gary, Williams Morrow, New York, 1979, p. 296 Until the general theory of relativity, Euclidean geometry had been accepted without question as the underlying structure of the universe ... Birkhoff and Von Neumann disproved the universality of classical logic ... A powerful awareness lies dormant in these discoveries: an awareness of the hitherto-unsuspected powers of the mind to mold 'reality' rather than the other way round. In this sense, the philosophy of physics is becoming indistinguishable from the philosophy of Buddhism, which is the philosophy of enlightenment. The Tao of Physics, Capra, F., Widewood House, London, 1975, p. 100 The essence of this experience ('awakening') is to pass beyond the world of intellectual distinction and opposites to reach the world of acintya, the unthinkable, where reality appears as undivided and undifferentiated. Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, Jayatilleke, K. N., Allen & Unwin, London 1963, p. 449 [About the cause-effect relationship in the Dhamma] ... a one-one correlation is established between the conditions constituting the cause and their effect. This is the scientific view of causation as opposed to the practical common-sense view. Zen and the Taming of the Bull, Rahula, W., Gordon Fraser, London, 1968, p. 42 What is nibbana? The only reasonable answer to this quite natural question is that it can never be answered in words correctly and satisfactorily because human language is too poor to express the real nature of absolute truth or the ultimate reality which is nibbana. A language is created by a mass of human beings to express things and ideas experienced by their sense organs and their mind. A supra-mundane experience like that of the absolute Truth is not of that category. Therefore, there can be no words to express that experience. Words are symbols representing things and ideas and these symbols do not and cannot convey the true nature of even ordinary things. Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism, Kalupahana, D. J., University of Hawaii, Honolulu, 1975, p. 98 . . . the causal principle as stated in the Pali Nikayas and the Chinese Agamas seems to include all the features of the scientific theory of causation--objectivity, uniqueness, necessity, conditionality, constant conjunction, productivity, relativity--as well as one-one correlation. (3) A Short Comment In order to explain or exposit the Buddha-Dhamma, the above mentioned scholars have made use of almost every significant trend of thought (except those philosophical techniques of Wittgenstein which are so much at home with the Buddha-Dhamma) in the Western world in a comparative sense, from meaning-oriented logical positivism to various scientific discourses. But we are perplexed, for less significant results have been accomplished. The point that will be made explicit in this connection is the failure on the part of these scholars and thinkers to provide a groundwork before attempting to elicit the logical nature of the key notions in the Dhamma. Hence they appear to oscillate between (i) positivism of the Vienna Circle and the Dhamma, (ii) certain concepts of scientific discourse and the Dhamma, and (iii) doctrines of 'reality' of the idealists and the Dhamma. These discourse have resulted in philosophical errors and confusions of contexts caused by their failure to elicit the criteria of meaning, aims and conceptual bases of those trends of thought of the Graeco-Roman conceptual structure. (4) The Aim The aim of this paper is to make the Buddha-Dhamma philosophical in a modem sense. This will be done through an application of conceptual tools or techniques to clarify the key Buddhist notions. Therefore, there is no system-building but simply analysis--philosophical analysis, which makes use of the following key philosophical tools from later Wittgenstein: (a) 'language-game'; (b) 'tool-simile'; (c) 'model'; (d) 'form of life'; and (e) 'conceptual family'. The key Buddhist notions to be analysed on the above bases are: (i) truth--saccam; [1] (ii) knowledge--anna [2] and (iii) emancipation--nibbana. (5) The Notion of Truth--Saccam The philosophical tool borrowed from Wittgenstein here is: 'Do not ask for the meaning; ask for the use'. We are not concerned in this section with raising the question 'what is truth' nor with attempting to formulate a solution. Instead, the following question is raised: "How did the Buddha use the word 'truth'?" To which, the following answer is noted: The 'truth' set rolling forth by the Buddha cannot be rolled back by a recluse or brahman or god or Mara or Brahma or by anyone else in the world. That is to say, it was a proclamation of the four Aryan truths, a teaching. [3] About the teaching: 'Suffering' is my teaching. The origin of suffering is my teaching. The cessation of suffering is my teaching. The path that leads to the cessation of suffering is my teaching. [4] The four noble truths are noted in this passage. The fourth truth which symbolises the path is the key as well as the most misunderstood one. The following issues are raised, primarily, to clarify the notions contained therein. They are as follows: (i) What is the logical nature of the notion of the eightfold noble path--ariyattangikamaaga? (ii) Is it ethical or empirical? (iii) If the eightfold noble path is the only way by which craving and clinging are eliminated, then what kind of action is expected to be performed? (iv) Can that kind of action (when performed) be characterised as wholesome--kusala? (v) Can it be meditative also? Let me begin this exegesis with the discourse about the noble quest. This discourse notes both the rediscovery of the 'truth' and the decision to preach the 'truth.' The Nikayas often note that the Buddha penetrated the 'truth' and decided to preach that 'truth' by way of some communicable ideas--the four noble truths. As notions, the four noble truths function to hold together all aspects of Buddhist philosophy that have to do with a human person's craving, clinging and emancipation. The Dhamma is the four truths--catusaccadhamma--the Buddha attained--ajjhagamama--by way of mastering them according to this discourse. The fourth noble truth is explained as 'ariyamagga'-the noble path. The notion of noble path represents, undoubtedly, that of the path of emancipation--the path of nibbana. In respect of the four noble truths preached by the Master, two points are made explicit: (1) The attainment (patilabba) of the truths is profound, is difficult to understand. It is an attainment and penetration by some kind of mastery which involves a do-it-yourself technique. Accordingly, the four noble truths are not hypotheses; nor are they empirical statements about the way things go in human life. Therefore, they are not verifiable in sense-experience. (2) The noble eightfold path which was known by way of super-perceptual knowledge (abhinna), is made known as the fourth truth. (1) above is metaphysical to us humans, but (2) is not. All the more so because it comes in the form of a procedural guide called the eightfold noble path in respect of emancipation. This is the 'teaching' we referred to previously. This 'teaching' or 'procedural guide' comprises eight components. The illumination, that is the effect of practice of the ethical norms embedded, made explicit in the procedural guide, marks the cooling of greed, hate and delusion, elimination of craving and clinging, to which the Buddha referred as nibbana. The attainment of nibbana is but an emancipation from the inflowing impulses of sensuous gratification; and, therefore, the word 'truth' is used in the Dhamma in the sense of 'saving truth'--a soteriology. Emancipation of the 'human person' from craving and clinging, is signified here. This use of the word 'truth' is different from the use of the word 'truth' in correspondence theories, coherence theories, pragmatic theories, scientific theories, Marxist theories, and in discourses on law and jurisprudence. At this juncture, it is worth noting generally that the Buddha-Dhamma is not attempting to discuss the criteria of meaning and truth. Instead, what is being suggested is the need to grasp Buddha's uses of the word 'truth'; and, of course, for this to be possible we need to 'play the language game'. (6) The Notion of Knowledge--anna The Wittgensteinean philosophical tool used here is 'engine idle'. Such key notions or words as (knowledge) (anna) and 'emancipation' (nibbana) readily follow from the Dhamma's procedural guide. However, they need to be rearranged into a conceptual family. If this is not accomplished, these notions or words may be pulled here and there, now and then, making "the engine idle." [5] Recently philosophers, especially those in the English-speaking world, have increasingly felt that epistemological issues arise wherever it is appropriate to speak of knowledge; hence, epistemological issues abound in science, mathematics, history, ethics, and religion. [6] To begin with, we contend that the Buddha's use of the word 'knowledge' is within a set soteriology-oriented scheme--family--and, therefore, does not have an epistemological basis. [7] It cannot be denied that notions such as truth and knowledge in the Buddha Dhamma invariably sound as if they are epistemological. However, the very logical strand of the Dhamma is such that the most that this notion of 'knowledge' could convey is a soteriology (Greek 'soteria' = English 'emancipation'). In other words the core of knowledge is emancipation, even though it appears juxtaposed with an epistemology. "The form of life" and "the language-game" [8] of the Dhamma are such that the notion of knowledge takes a striking turn to soteriology and is not concerned solely with epistemology per se. 'Nibbana' or 'the blowing out' is the logical end of moral excellence (sile), mental discipline (samadhi) and wisdom (panna). This kind of knowledge, therefore, cannot be epistemological in a weak sense or a strong one. The impossibility of having clear families of notions recognisable as ontological or epistemological, is also clearly evident. Where does a soteriological family of notions stand pertaining to the Buddha-Dhamma? Certainly, the family of notions of the Dhamma accommodates 'knowledge' but in a non-epistemological sense. This is a case in which we wish to say that one could be misled by the forms of expression [9], if one is unaware of the difference in the grammar of the two significant uses. Wittgenstein notes this point thus: "That the confusions which occupy us arise when language is like an engine idling, not when it is doing work." [10] On this count, Johansson's "perceptual facts", "psychological factors in the process of rebirth" are but notions used, simply, without context; they are outside the Dhamma-message (or the Buddhist language-game). To amplify, Johansson states: (see quote no 1 above) "... it is a well known fact that, according to Buddhism, all living beings are reborn in accordance with their activities". However, there is a failure to master a clear view of the use of words within the logical boundary of the Dhamma-discourse. This point is elaborated in the following way: that 'kamma' in the Buddha's message is an ethical notion rather than a factual one. Besides, to say that "'kamma' takes one from birth to birth", to put it differently, if understood within the domain of factuality (empirical fact), gives rise to a confusion of contexts. And, therefore, to the notion that Buddhist ethical notions (or for that matter any other ethical notion), because of their value-nature, are accommodated outside factuality. The point is highlighted when the positive statement "kamma takes one from birth to birth" (p) is negated to read as "kamma does not take one from birth to birth" (q) The negative statement (q) cannot be established by way of factual evidence; no more can the positive statement (p). Genuinely Buddhist notions, words, statements, etc. are neither true nor false empirically since they are characteristic of such natures as eternity (sanatano), necessity (avitathata), and invariability (anannathata). [11] They are assigned the truth-value 'true', figuratively only. That is to say, they are values which are made explicit by way of ethical (value) statements and judgements. And, therefore, the Buddhist truths (or values) are not liable to falsity simply because of their nature. Within the Buddhist conceptual structure, accordingly, kamma-activity is ethically true (value-judgement), but has no meaning, drive and life outside this arena. The poverty of Johansson's argument, hence, must be clear. Wittgenstein strengthens this view: "A main source of our failure to understand is that we do not command a clear view of the use of our words." [12] Emancipatory final knowledge is referred to by the Buddha in this way: "I do not say that one can win the final knowledge at the very beginning; it is attainable by way of gradual discipline, a gradual mode of action and conduct." [13] The gradual discipline comprises: (a) the practice of virtuous life (ariyena silakkhandena samanna-gato); [14] (b) the restraint of the senses (indriyasamvara); (c) the developments of mindfulness (satisampajanna); and (d) the elimination of the five impediments (panchanivaranapaha-ya). [15] These actions jointly characterise the equilibrium of perfection of equanimity and mindfulness (upekkhasatipari-suddhim). It is in this state that the six-fold super-perceptual knowledge is manifested. The sixth super-perceptual knowledge (abhinna) gives the certainty that emancipation has been attained. This is referred to as knowledge vision of emancipation (vimuttinanadassana). Reaching a stage of elimination of craving and clinging on the one hand and reaping the effects of knowledge vision of emancipation on the other are but characteristics of a state of mind. The Majjhima Nikaya.I.167, for instance, notes the unshakability of this emancipatory knowledge. The point is emphasised again and again by the notions (i) sammadannavimuatta (freed by perfect profound knowledge, [16] and (ii) annaya nibbuta dhira (knowing, having attained nibbana here and now). [17] The implications of the above are as follows: (i) that it is possible to lay down once and for all what has to be done, if the final knowledge is to be attained, in the sense of a state of mind; (ii) that knowledge can be founded as a state of mind; (iii) that the procedural guide called the eightfold noble path guarantees the attainment of the final knowledge--a state of mind--anna. This is a logical end, a certain end, without an alternative. When the Dhamma's soteriology is clear, it is simply a misplaced emphasis to bring about 'causality-talk' or 'science-talk' as done by writers such as Capra and Jayatilleke. Probabilistic 'causality-talk' or 'science-talk' has no relevance; they simply result in profanity. (7) The Notion of Emancipation (a blowing out) The Wittgensteinean philosophical tool utilised here is "In pursuit of the purest essence". escribed by the Buddha is one who has eliminated craving and clinging. According to the Buddhist language-game, he has attained nibbana. Often, at this stage, it is not unusual to enquire: "What is nibbana?" This query, however, has bred confusions of contexts as well as high-flown dialectics. W. Rahula's statement provides one such illustration. He claims that 'nibbana' or 'supra-mundane reality' is inexpressible in languages created by human beings. Capra, too comes close to this view when he says "... the essence of this experience ('awakening') is to pass beyond the world of intellectual distinction ..." Both these views not only create ostensible problems as there is a basic failure to understand the nature of the Dhamma's language-game, but also run the risk of being out of date. That is, if the Dhamma's language-game is accepted as the original home of the word 'nibbana', then problems regarding it cannot arise. Admittedly, if it is used in a way to refer to a thing and attempt to grasp the essence of it, Wittgenstein's following reminder is timely: "When philosophers use a word--'knowledge,' 'being,' 'object,' 'I,' 'proposition,' 'name,' and try to grasp the essence of a thing, one must always ask oneself: is the word ever actually used in this way in the language-game which is its original home?" [18] Now, the key issue is: are we to agree with Rahula here? If the answer is affirmative, philosophical extrapolation, which is so much at home with Buddhist notions, needs to be done away with. Now let us see how the Buddha used the word 'nibbana' from the following passages. (i) 'possessing naught, and cleaving unto naught, That is the isle, the incomparable isle. Nibbana do I call it, Kappa (said the Exalted one)--That is the isle.' [19] (ii) 'Formerly, I, monks, as well as now, lay down simply suffering and the cessation of suffering.' [20] (iii) 'For this monk, is the highest aryan truth, that is to say nibbana, that is not liable to falsity.' (iv) '... this is peaceful and excellent, namely, the cessation of all processes, the abandoning of all limitations, the elimination of desire, dispassion, cessation, nibbana.' [22] Is it not fair to maintain that the above contentions, together with other similar ones which are apparent in all strata of the Nikayas, suggest an explanation, exposition and description of the word 'nibbana' in the Dhamma's language-game? The Dhamma does not posit 'something' other than the goal of holy life, namely, 'cooling of craving and clinging'. According to Rahula's view of common-sense language(s), by implication, there can be words which lack representations at the lowest point of the gradation. That is, words can be schematised in grades of being nearest to reality or farthest away from it. In this scheme, it is logically possible to have words which lack representations. If so, obviously, they should be empty. This view of language arises when what is looked at is a form of words and not the use made of the form of words. Our view is that the Dhamma's statements, which are framed out of the words of the then ethical language(s), need to be given attention by way of the use made of the form of words rather than the form of words itself. Language approached in this way brings about the following: (i) it frees us from the dead-end view of word-symbol-representation theory and clarifies and intensifies our understanding; (ii) it prevents us from the pursuit of the venerable bugbear, as J. L. Austin puts it, by sending us in pursuit of the essence of a thing, or sending us in pursuit of chimeras according to Wittgenstein. [23] When the Buddhist language is approached in the above fashion it brings about greater understanding and helps to dispel the many misconceptions in which it is clothed. In conclusion it would be fair to say that Buddhism can be best appreciated by using a sotoriological conceptual framework. It would be a mistake to unravel Buddhism through the sole use of epistemological or ontological notions. NOTES [1] The Suttanipata (London, Pali Text Society) verse no. 884. [2] The Majjhima Nikaya (London, Pali Text Society) Vol. III. 29. [3] Ibid., III. 248. [4] The Digha Nikaya, (London, Pali Text Society) Vol. I. 191. [5] WITTGENSTEIN, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations (Oxford, Basil Blackwell) p. 51e. [6] HAMLYN, D. W. (1977) Theory of Knowledge (London, Macmillan) p. 288. [7] WITTGENSTEIN, op. cit., p. 116e. [8] WITTGENSTEIN, op. cit., p. 11e. [9] Ibid., p. 168e [10] Ibid., p. 51e. [11] The Samyutta Nikaya (London, Pali Text Society) Vol. II.26. [12] WITTGENSTEIN, op. cit., p. 49e. [13] The Majjhima Nikaya (London, Pali Text Society) Vol. I. 479-80. [14] Ibid., 346. [15] Ibid., 347. [16] The Majjhima Nikaya (London, Pali Text Society) Vol. II. 43. [17] Ibid. [18] Wittgenstein, op. cit., p. 48e. [19] The Suttanipata, op. cit., verse no.1091-1094. [20] The Majjhima Nikaya, Vol. I., op. cit., 140. [21] The Majjhima Nikaya, Vol. III, op. cit., p. 245. [23] The Majjhima Nikaya, Vol. I, op. cit., 436. [24] WITTGENSTEIN, op. cit., p. 44e.