Hastings Center Report
Vol. 28 No. 1 Jan/Feb.1998
Pp.41-43
Copyright by Hastings Center Report
As the issues and problems facing the field of bioethics expand in audience and importance, new perspectives and traditions are entering the conversation. In his book, Buddhism and Bioethics, Damien Keown takes on the daunting challenge of formulating and introducing a Buddhist voice to the bioethics discussion. This contribution to the field of "applied normative ethics" is the first systematic attempt to apply Buddhist principles to contemporary issues in bioethics. Keown's task is multifold: posit a set of Buddhist principles by a process of induction from canonical monastic rules, discern and establish Buddhist concepts and vocabulary analogous to existing bioethics' rhetoric, and provide substantive "Buddhist" judgments on particular debates currently raging in the medical ethics arena. This is no easy cross-cultural and interdisciplinary project. In setting up his model, which Keown claims is for the general reader, he provides thumbnail sketches of Buddhism and relevant Buddhist teachings such as karma, no-self, and rebirth. He then appropriates elements of Aristotelian ethics and natural law. In particular, he adopts the Aristotelian position that what it means for humans to flourish involves a specific goal or telos to be realized through the cultivation of particular practices. He draws from natural law theory the claim that objectivity in ethics is possible. Through reflection on basic forms of human good and ends, one can arrive at objective principles regarding which sorts of acts are reasonable and which are not. With the particular elements of his approach defined and his intellectual framework presented, Buddhism, for Keown, is best understood as a teleological virtue ethic: "In Buddhist terms, the goal of human perfection is nirvana and this is attained through the process of moral and intellectual self-transformation, which comes about through following the Eightfold Path" (p. xii). Keown asserts that the bases for such integration of Buddhist doctrine with Aristotelian and natural law precepts are spelled out in detail in his previous book, entitled The Nature of Buddhist Ethics. Thus he is satisfied with the brief descriptions of the elements of his model, and the main methodological focus of Buddhism and Bioethics establishes a set of basic principles with which to enter the bioethics conversation. While recognizing the diversity of perspectives within the Buddhist tradition itself, Keown relies primarily on the canonical and commentarial literature of the Theravada school. Such allegiance informs his admitted "fundamentalist" orientation--asserting that problems of scriptural interpretation can be overcome and moral truth discovered. He claims that "For Buddhism, scripture is the embodiment of the Buddhas moral insight" (p. 15) and that it "sees its moral teachings as the expression of universal principles" (p. 21). Drawing from the five basic precepts of moral conduct laid down by the Buddha [the prohibitions of the taking of life, stealing, sexual misconduct, lying, and taking of intoxicants found in the Vinaya, the monastic code texts of the Pali Canon] and the Buddhist emphasis on wisdom and compassion, he formulates three Buddhist basic goods: life, knowledge, and friendship. The cultivation and realization of these goods constitutes human fulfillment, or enlightenment. From these basic goods he deduces corresponding principles-given the basic good, it is always wrong to choose against that basic good. Therefore, his principles are formulated as follows: it is always wrong to choose against life, knowledge, and friendship. Equipped with these principles, Keown turns his focus to the questions confronting bioethics and applies these goods and this principlist logic to a comprehensive list of contemporary issues, such as abortion, embryo research, cloning, reproductive technology, euthanasia, and physician-assisted suicide. Such a method produces some interesting and challenging conclusions. Keown's characterization of Buddhism as a teleological virtue ethic is an accurate and fruitful one, and his presentation of basic Buddhist goods does hold tremendous potential for future dialogue in bioethics. However, Keown focuses mainly on life as a basic good, and never really develops the roles of the other two goods, knowledge and friendship. While the basic good of life arguably deserves primacy as both a good in itself and the precondition for the fulfillment of all other goods, knowledge and friendship remain only cursorily discussed. Furthermore, in his adaptation of principlist methods, he appears to work only in the realm of absolutes with no mention of prima facie principles or guidelines for resolving conflicts among principles. Keown begins with textually supported discussions of the Buddhist definitions of biological life and death. But in his application of his basic good of life, the term life is much broader, perhaps overly so. He assesses acts in light of the basic good of life with biological terminology in some cases and with a purely metaphysical approach in others. The intrinsic value of life as he presents it needs further explication. This basic good seems to trump all others, a dubious position for a Buddhist voice. The basic good of knowledge is presented as knowledge of the Dharma (the teachings of the Buddha), with what appears to be a quick conflation to a knowledge of right and wrong. Friendship is presented as the paradigm for interpersonal relations, and more appropriate, Keown feels, than focusing on compassion. The relationship between knowledge and compassion is a rich and foundational one in Buddhism, and life itself as a basic good cannot stand apart from this relationship without failing to be a Buddhist view. In the absence of a full exploration into the two goods other than life, the "virtue" component of Keown's Buddhist ethic is distractingly underexamined. Moreover, his integration of Aristotelian ethics and natural law with basic Buddhist concepts becomes suspect. For example, he refers to the Aristotelian ideal of friendship, which cannot be said to imply the type of universal friendship he posits as the Buddhist basic good. Another potential synthesis problem involves Keown's equating Dharma with natural law. The foundational premise of a conception of Dharma as "the immutable laws of both the natural and moral orders" invites problems at the very onset of his project. Many Buddhist scholars would object to such an understanding of the Dharma. For example, some, especially scholars of the Mahayana tradition, would claim that the Buddhas teachings are a matter of upaya, or skillful means, an approach that includes right application of knowledge and compassion in a situation-specific moral calculus. Much of the bioethics debate hinges on issues of intention, aim, and motive-distinctions that Keown rightly addresses. On paper, most of the relevant bioethics elements are here: definitions of life and death, distinctions between killing and letting die, motive and aim, and different ethical orientations such as consequentialism. However, Keown fails to examine systematically the one natural component of the relationship between his basic goods--upaya--that informs "virtuous" Buddhist action. Upaya as "skillful" means is another area where fruitful dialogue between bioethics and Buddhism lies, and not developing it requires explanation. Nevertheless, Keown's book is an excellent first step in introducing and formulating the Buddhist vocabulary and approach necessary for productive engagement of contemporary issues in bioethics. It succeeds in presenting a skillfully and creatively crafted Buddhist voice. Keown's applications, despite some problematic initial claims, are faithful to the Theravada tradition and offer an invitation to further dialogue with the field of bioethics. ~~~~~~~~ by Leslie Rezac -------------------