`Atta, Niratta`, and `Anatta` in the early Buddhist literature

中華佛學學報第六期 1993.07 出版
(pp. 391-424)

Biswaded Mukherjee
Visiting Professor,
Chung-Hwa Institute of Buddhist Studies



                                  391 頁

          `Atta, Niratta`, and `Anatta` in the early Buddhist
          literature

          Biswadeb Mukherjee

          Visiting Professor,
          Chung-Hwa Institute of Buddhist Studies

          Summary
               The present article deals with the non-Buddhist
          concepts  of `atta`  and their refutaion  through the
          doctrine  of `anatta` .  This article is divided into
          five sections.
          
               Section  I discusses  `Nikaya`  passages  which
          states that the `atta` is not existent either in the
          sphere  of the  Conditioned  or in the realm  of the
          Unconditioned.  It  is  nothing  but  a  figment  of
          imagination.
          
               Section  II refers  to the  different  opinions
          held by scholars  as to the proper  implications  of
          the term `atta` .  Except  for the lone  voice  of E.
          Conze  who found similarity  between  the `atta` and
          the `Purusa` of the `Samkhya` , all other scholars
          who cared  to ponder  over this  problem, seem to be
          preoccupied  with the relationship  that could exist
          between  the `atta` and the `atman` of the `Upanisads` .
          This  may be due to the fact  that  these  two
          terms-- `atta`  and `atman` --are   philologically
          identical.   The  philological   identity   led  the
          scholars readily to accept the view that these terms
          are also philosophically  identical  without  making
          any   further    investigation    into   the   exact
          connotations of these two terms. The need for a more
          objective study of the problem of equation of `atta`
          and `atman` is obvious, and a suitable  methodology
          for such a study has been suggesed.
          
              Section III delineates  the main features of the
          thoughts of the `Sasvatavadins` , `Ekaccasassatavadins` ,
          the `ucchedavadins`  and the followers  of
          the  `Satkayadrsti` .  They  were  the  chief
          propagators  of the `atta` heresies rejected  by the
          Buddha.
          
              Section IV, Part A contations  the criticism  of
          all these heresies meant for the Buddhist monks. The
          validity  of such a criticism  mainly  rests  on the
          Buddha's  claim to superior and higher knowledge  of
          which the heretics know nothing.  Part B of the same
          Section  offers  us the following  two  patterns  of
          reasonings  which  were  ultimately  meant  for  the
          non-Buddhist   ascetics   and   employed   for   the
          refutation  of the different  `atta`  heresies except
          the `Ucchedavada` :  i) To reject the opponent's view
          by  showing  the  internal  contradictions, a method
          which  was later  followed  by `Nagarjuna`  with
          great success;  ii) To temporarily  accept a part of
          the opponent's  view in order  to show that the view
          as such  is unacceptable.  This  may be taken  as an
          instance of skillfulness of means praised so much in
          the `Mahayana` .
          
               Section  V comes  to the  conclusion  that  the
           `anatta` doctrine  was mainly formulated  keeping in
          view the `sasvatavada` and the `Ucchedavada` .
          This is in conformity  with  some statements  in the
          buddhist texts that the buddha preached the `anatta`
          doctrine as a middle way between these two extremes.
          It is also clear that the `atta` concepts  of the
           `sasvatavadins` and the `Uccedavadins` cannot be
          identical with the `atman` of the `Upanisads` .  The
          Buddhist  sages  were aware of the fact that the `atta`
          rejected  by the buddha  is ' `ahankara-visayah` '
          whereas the `Upanisadic  Atman` is ' `Buddhanamvisayah` '.




                                  393 頁

                               I

              The doctrine of `anatta` forms the keynote of
        the teachings of the Buddha and literally means that
        the `atta` is non-existent. The denial of the `atta`
        finds expression in the following statment ascribed
        to the Buddha in the Samyutta `Nikaya`: "Sabbam
        bhikkhave `aniccam/sabbam` bhikkhave
        `dukkham/sabbam` bhikkhave `anatta`".(1) The chapter
        just preceeding the one from which we have quoted
        the three statements, contains such expressions as
        "sabbe bhikkhave `jaradhammam`......`vyadhidhammam`
        ......`maranadhammam`......`samkilesadhamam`" etc.
        (2) These statements leave no doubt that in all
        these cases we have to take the term 'sabba' as
        indicating the things condition. So we find that
        'sabba' is a technical term and stands for the
        '`samskrta dharma'`. This conclusion of ours is
        confirmed by the definition of 'sabba' as given in
        the Sabbavaggo of the `Salayatana-samyutta`(3):
        "`Kin` ca bhikkhave `sabbam/cakkhu` ceva `rupa`
        ca/`sotanca sadda` ca/`ghananca gandha` ca/`jihva
        rasa` ca/kayo ca `photthabba` ca/mano ca `dhamma`
        ca/idam vuccati bhikkhave `sabbam`" According to
        this definition 'sabba' means eye and the foms, the
        nose and the smells, the ear and the sounds, the
        tongue and the tastes, the body and the tangible
        things, the mind and the mental objects. Here the
        term 'sabba'means twelve `ayatanas`. In a more
        elaborate way the Buddha explains the same term
        while giving instructions on the giving up of the
        'sabba'. He states that eye, form, eye-contact,
        eye-consciousness and the different feeling due to
        eye-contact are to be renounced. Similarly he
        preaches with references to other sense organs(4).
        Thus the term 'sabba' fully covers the category of
        'samskrta-dharma' and the statement "`sabbam
        anatta`" means the conditioned is without any soul
        ────────────
        (1) S. Vol.Ⅳ,p.28,ⅩⅩⅩⅤ,43-45(PTS,London, 1894)
        (2) Ibid ⅩⅩⅩⅤ,34-38
        (3) Ibid,p.15, ⅩⅩⅩⅤ,23
        (4) Katamo ca bhikkhave `sabbapahanayo
            dhammo/cakkhum bhikkhave `pahatabbam`/`rupa
            pahatabba`/`cakkhuvinnanam pahatabbam`/
            cakkhusamphasso `pahatabbo`/yam `pidam
            cakkhusamphassopaccaya` uppajjati `vedayitam
            sukham va dukkham va` adukkham `asukham va`/
            tam pi `pahatabbam`/(`Samyutta`, Ⅳ, pp15-16,
            ⅩⅩⅩⅤ, 24 (PTS, London, 1894)

                                  394 頁

        (soul).

              But what about the Unconditioned? Is it also
        devoid of `atta`? Walpolo Rahulo thinks that it is,
        and refers to the three statements from Dhammapada
        in support of his contention(5). These statements
        which are very similar to the passage from the
        `Samyutta Nikaya` quoted above are as follows: i)
        sabbe `sankhara dukkha`, ii) sabbe `sankhara anicca`.
        iii), sabbe `dhamma anatta`. Rahulo thinks that while
        the phrase sabbe `sankhara` indicates the things
        conditioned, the phrase sabbe `dhamma` refers to
        both the Conditioned and the Unconditioned. But it
        is difficult to accept this interpretation. We may
        hold that the word 'sabbe' should have the same
        meaning as the term 'sabbam'. viz. the conditioned
        things, and it is unreasonable to assume that the
        scope of the word 'sabba' while occuring together
        with the term 'dhamma' is so extended as to include
        even the opposite meaning, the Unconditioned.
        Moreover the phrase 'sabbe dhamma' has been used
        many times in the Buddhist scriptures to mean only
        the Conditioned. The Karatalaratna, a comparatively
        late work written by `Bhavaviveka`, described
        '`sarvadharmah`' as being of dependent origin
        (`sarvadharmah`......`pratityasamutpannah`......`nih-
        svabhavah`).(6) Again in the Culasaccakasutta of the
        Majjhima Nikaya (7) it is stated: "`rupam bhikkhave
        aniccam, vedana anicca`,......`vinnanam aniccam`,
        `rupam bhikkhave anatta`, `vedana`......`sanna`......
        `samkhara`......`vinnanam anatta`, sabbe `samkhara
        anicca`, sabbe `dhamma anatta` ti. "Here both the
        phrases 'sabbe dhamma`, and sabbe `samkhara`
        obviously refer to the five skandhas. That only the
        conditioned things are meant here become evident
        when in the same sutta (8) we meet with a discussion
        on things which are both `anicca` and `anatta`.
        `Nibbana` is not included in this discussion. The
        `Upasivamanapuccha` of the Sutta `Nipata`(9)(1076)
        states that in case of `nibbana` all dharmas are
        destroyed (sabbesu
        ────────────
        (5) Rahulo, What the Buddha taught (Grove Press,
           INC.New York, 1962), pp.57-58; Dhammapada,
           Chapter 20, verses 5-7
        (6) `Swami Vidyaranya`, Bauddha Dharma O `Darsan`,
            p.16(West Bengal State Book Board, Calcutta,
            1984)
        (7) Majjhima, Vol.I,p.280(Nava Nalanda Ed.),
            p.228(PTS Ed.); also see, `Samyutta` Vol. Ⅲ,
            p.132
        (8) Ibid. 282-87(Nava Nalanda Ed.)

                                  395 頁

        dhammesu upahatesu). Sabbe `dhamma` has been
        explained as skandhas and `ayatanas` in the
        Cullaniddesa,(10) making it clear that `nibbana` is
        outside the scope of this phrase. In the
        `Mahaparinibbanasutta`(11) Aniruddha explains
        buddha's parinibbana as 'vimokkho' of consciousness
        (pajjotass'eva `nibbanam` vimokkho cataso). The term
        'vimokkho' has been explained by Buddhaghoso in the
        Sumangalavilasini(12) as freedom from all dharmas
        (vimokkho'ti kenaci dhemmena `anabarana`). Thus the
        testimony of the `Suttanipata` and the `Maha
        parinibbanasutta` confirms that the phrase '`sabbe
        dhamma`' does not include `nibbana within its scope.

              So the things conditioned were definitely held
        to be devoid of `atta`. But was the nirvana, the
        Unconditioned also bereft of `atta`? Is the `atta`
        non-existent with reference to the Unconditioned
        also? In the `Udana`(13) `nibbana` is described as
        `anatta`which is rightly glossed as `atta-virahita`
        in `Paramatthadipam`. Thus the `atta` is
        non-existent either as a `samskrta-dharma` or as an
        `asamskrta-dharma`. The `atta` is nothing but a
        figment of imagination.

                                 Ⅱ

        ────────────
        (9) PTS, London, 1913, The group of Discourses Ⅱ,
            p.121 (PTS, London, 1992)
       (10) Cullaniddesa, (PTS. London, 1988) p.177, also
            see, The Group of Discourses Ⅱ p.376
       (11) `Digha`, VolⅡ,p.157. The line "`pajjotasseva
            nibbanam vimokkho cetaso`" is translated in
            Dialogues of the Buddha, Pt. Ⅱ, p.176, as 'Even
            as a bright flame dies away, so was the last
            emancipation of his heart'. 'pajjota' is
            translated as a lamp while '`nibbana`' is taken
            to be blowing out of a lamp'. On the other hand
            M.Walche understand 'pajjota' in the sense of
            the 'Illumined One' and translate the same line
            as 'By `Nibbana` the. Illumined's mind is freed'
            (Thus Have I Heard, London, 1987; p.271). Both
            these translations are not fully satisfactory
            PTS translates 'eva' as 'like' while it would
            have been better to render it as 'just, surely,
            indeed'. Walche omits it. As 'pajjotassa
            `nibbana`' is compared with 'vimokkho cetaso',
            it would be more appropriate to translate as the
            'nibbana of the Enlightened One'. So the sentence
            may be rendered as follows: 'The `nibbana` of
            the Enlightened one is, indeed, the release of
            mind'.
       (12) `Sumangala-vilasini`, PartⅡ, p.595(PTS, London,
            1971)

                                  396 頁

              To know the reason behind the denial of `atta`
        we have first to be clear about the exact
        implication of the term `atta`. Scholars differ as
        to the precise sense in which this term has been
        used. But before their views were discussed it is
        necessary to point out that the `prakrt` word `atta`
        is the same as `atman` in Sanskrit. This
        philological identification has led to philosophical
        misunderstanding among the scholars. Some scholars
        automatically take `atta` to be the `Atman` of the
        `Upanisads`. They think that the philosophical
        implications of these two terms-`atta` and
        `atman`-are identical and consequently the doctrine
        of `anatta` came to mean for them the refutation of
        the `Upanisadic Atman`. The scholars belonging to
        this
        ────────────
       (13) P.Steinthal in his edition of the `Udana` (PTS,
            London, 1982), p.80 adopts the following reading
            of the relevant verse:
               'duddasam anattam `nama`, na hi saccam
            sudassanam `patividdha tanha janato`, passato
            n'atthi `kincanan`' ti'.
            In his translation F.L.Woodward reads 'anantam'
            (infinite) in place of anattam (Verses of Uplift,
            The Minor Anthologies of the Canon, Pt. Ⅱ, PTS
            London, 1985, p.98). I prefer the reading
            'anattam' due to the following considerations:
            Steinthal gives the variant reading 'anattam'
            given in the commentary (anatatan ti `pathati`)
            called `Paramattha-dipani` which was copied in
            Sinhalese script for the PTS. This transcript
            which he calls 'C' often gives right information
            and corrects the incorrect readings of the other
            manuscripts (see, Stienthal, Udana, p.ⅤⅢ).
            This commentary explains 'anattam' as
            '`atta-virahitam`'. Another manuscript which he
            calls 'B' as well as the Nava-Nalanda Ed. of the
            `Udana` fallow this reading. There is no reason
            why the reading 'ananttam' should not be
            accepted. On the other hand it is difficult to
            agree with Woodward who accepts the reading
            'anantam', as it is found only in the
            `Nidanatthakatha` of `Dhammapalacariya` (Ed.
            F.L.Woodward, PTS, London, 1977, p.393).
            `Nidanatthakatha` explains as follows:
            '`niccasvabhavatta` anta-virahitam
            amaranadhammam anirodham amatam ti attho'. 'As
            nibbana is permanent by nature, it is without an
            end, beyond death and cessation; it is
            immortal'. It is obvious that this definition of
            `nibbana` also excludes `atta`.
            Actually speaking no scriptural evidence is
            needed to prove that `nibbana` is devoid of
            `atta`. The concept of `atta` is such that it is
            automatically excluded from the domain of
            `nibbana`.

                                  397 頁

        group have an unfaltering faith in the Buddha as the
        unique preacher of the True Law, and as such harbour
        no weakness for the honoured traditions of the
        `Upanisads`. The view of Walpolo Sri Rahulo, an
        worthy representative of this group, will be
        pressented later. On the other hand those scholars
        who hold both the Buddha and the `Upsnisads` in high
        esteem do not subscribe to this view. Let us take
        note of the opinion of Radhakrishnan (14) who
        belongs to this second group of scholars. According
        to him the Buddha clearly tells us what the soul
        (`atta`) is not, though he does not give us any
        clear account of what it is. It is, however, wrong
        to think that there is no soul according to the
        Buddha. In support of his opinion Radhakrishnan (15)
        refers to the dialogue between the wondering ascetic
        Vacchagotta which, according to him, shows that
        something there is, though it is not the empirical
        self. In another place (16) he refers to this
        empirical self and states that it is the false view
        that clamours for the perpetual continuation of this
        small self, which the Buddha refutes. This, (17)
        according to Radhakrishnan, also agrees with the
        statement of the Buddha that the self is neither the
        same nor different from the skandhas. He further
        states (18): "It is also clear that the reduction
        of the self to a number of skandhas is not ultimate.
        If the self is merely an impermanent compounded of
        body and mind......then when it disappears then
        there is nothing which is delivered......Freedom
        becomes extinction. But `Nirvana` is timeless
        existence and so the Buddha admit the reality of a
        timeless self."

              Radhakrishanan appers to be of the opinion
        that the term '`atta`' which he translates as self
        has been used in two different senses. One meaning
        of `atta` is the small self or empirical self which
        the Buddha rejects through the doctrine of `anatta`.
        The other implication of the term `atta` is the ture
        self which is same as `nirvana` and is accepted by
        the Buddha. It is the identity of this true self
        with other things that the buddha rejects.

              We may now discuss the opinion of Rahulo who
        represents the other group
        ────────────
       (14) Indian Philosophy, Vol. I,P.386(George Allen &
            Unwin, London, 1977)
       (15) Ibid. p.386
       (16) Ibid. p.388, note 1
       (17) Ibid. p.387
       (18) Ibid. p.451

                                  398 頁

        of scholars. While explaining the doctrine of
        `anatta` Rahulo (19) refers to the different
        concepts of `atman`, even the concept of
        Brahman-`Atman` of the `Upanisads and holds that the
        buddha was unique in rejecting all such doctrines
        through the doctrine of `anatta`. "The idea of an
        abiding, immortal substance in man or outside,
        whether it is called `Atman`, I, soul, self, or ego,
        is considered only a false belief, a mental
        projection. This is the Buddhist doctrine of
        `antta`(20). So it appears that by the doctrine of
        `anatta` the Buddha was denying `atta` "which was
        accepted by every other philosophico-religious
        system". Rahulo seems to suggest in not so ambiguous
        term that even the Brahman-`Atman` concept of the
        `Upanisads` stands hereby negated.

              It is clear that the concept of the
        `Upanisadic Atman` acts as a powerful background in
        in fluencing the formulations of both the
        above-mentioned views. Conze, (21) on the other hand,
        propounds a different theory which is not connected
        with the `Upanisadic Atamn` in any way. He is not
        sure what notions of an `ataman` were denied by the
        Buddha, but he believes that these notions are of two
        kinds, e.g. i) the ideas implied in the use of 'I'
        and 'mine', and ii) the philosophical opinion of the
        `Samkhya` and `Vaisesika`. The basic formula absence
        of a self is confined to the five skandhas, and
        nothing is said either way about its existence quite
        apart from them. The Buddha never taught that the
        self is not, only that it cannot be apprehended.

              It is obvious that the solution of this knotty
        problem hinges on the proper understanding of the
        nature of `atta` that was rejected by the Buddha. It
        is really strange that none of the scholars who
        suggested the equation of `atta` either with the
        `Upanisadic` Brahman-`Atman` or with some other
        non-buddhist concepts ever tried to clearly enunciate
        what this `atta` is. Any such suggestion without
        first defining the concept of `atta` is bound to be
        methodologically unscientific and unconvincing.

              To arrive at a more objective conclusion the
        following approach may be suggested. On the one hand
        we should study those materials from the `Nikaya` and
        ────────────
       (19) Rahulo, What the Buddha taught, p.51
       (20) Ibid. p.55
       (21) The Buddhist Thought in India, pp.38-39 (George
            Allen & Unwin, London, 1962)

                                  399 頁

        `Agama` which are more or less descriptive in
        nature. Such materials provide us with legends and
        other informantions about the `atta` philosophy
        dominant in the region where the Buddha was
        preaching his `anatta` doctrine, and so engaged his
        attention. The reason for doing so is the
        justifiable surmise that the `atta` concept or
        concepts, the negation of which forms the core of
        buddhism, should find some mention in this
        descriptive type of scripture. On the other hand we
        should carefully scrutinise another type of material
        contained in the Buddhist scripture which is more
        critical and philosophical in nature, and acquaints
        us with detailed arguments justifying the rejection
        of the `atta` philosophy. Out of such study will
        also emerge the `atta` concept or concepts which the
        Buddha was rejecting. The study of these two types
        of materials will enable us to form a complete idea
        of the different `atta` concepts the Buddha
        discarded as false views. It is only then we would
        be in a position to reliably know whether the
        `Upanisadic` concept of `Atman-Brahman` was rejected
        or not.

              The major non-buddhist concepts of `atta`
        criticised in the `Nikayas and `Agamas` many be
        broadly divided nito four main categories dealing
        with a) `Satkayadrsti`, b), `Sasvatavada`, C)
        `Ekaccassatavada`, and d) `Ucchedavada`. We will
        discuss these heresies in the order given here.

                             Ⅲ

              a)`Satkayadrsti`: In the `Samyutta Nikaya`(22)
        we come across the following description of a false
        view which later came to be known as `Satkayadrsti`:
        "Those recluses and Brahmanas who while seeing in
        various ways see the `atta`(soul), they actually see
        the five aggregates of attachment or any of them.
        Which five? In this connection, monks, an uneducated
        ordinary person......envisages matter as a soul, or a
        soul possessing matter, or matter in a soul, or a
        soul in matter. Or he envisages, feeling, perception,
        the gormative forces, or consciousness as a soul,
        possessed by a soul, in a soul, or soul in them.
        Envisaging thus he gets a thought "I am"......Being
        ignorant he thinks this, or "I am this" or "I shall
        be" "I shall not be" or I shall be material "or" I
        shall be having perception "or" I shall be
        ────────────
       (22) `Samyutta`, Vol.Ⅲ. 46f.; Taisho, Vol.Ⅱ,
            p.11b1ff. A.K. Warder, Indian Buddhism, pp.123ff

                                  400 頁

        without perception (`a-samjnin`)" or "I shall have
        neither perception nor non-perception. But one who
        is educated, abandons ignorance and gets knowledge
        ......and does not have any of these thoughts."

              The passage quoted above shows that the `atta`
        in which these recluses and `Brahmanas` believed
        could be in four different ways connected with the
        five skandhas and this connection is constant. The
        existence of an `atta` without any reference to the
        skandhas was unthinkable. This association of the
        soul with the skandhas gave rise to certain
        ego-centric thoughts in which both these elements-the
        soul and the skandhas-are present, e.g. "I am this"
        "I shall be material" etc.

              Here we have a succinct description of a false
        view that draws our attention to its two main
        features: 1) `atta` refers to an individual soul
        whose essence consists of an awareness of 'I' (22a);
        2) `atta` is invariably connected with the skandhas.
        Its existence is always conceived in association with
        skandhas. This heresy, as already noted, came to be
        known as `satkayadrsti`(Pali: `Sakkayaditthi`). The
        term `satkaya` refers to the five aggregates of
        attachment (`pancupadanakkhandha`)(23) and
        `Satkayadrsti` to a false view that fails to see the
        skandhas merely as skandhas, but always views them
        through the prism of an `atta`. The most subtle form
        of `satkayadrsti` is discernible in the feeling "I
        am" which lingers in anybody who is spiritually below
        the status of an arhat. He may no longer consciously
        believe in
        ────────────
       (22a) In the Alagaddupamasuttam of the Majjhima
             `Nikaya` (PTS), Vol. I, pp.138ff. (Nalanda Ed.),
             Vol.I,pp.185ff. We read that the feelings of 'I'
             and 'mine' are interdependent. And with "I" and
             "mine" to be really and truly existing, the
             possibility of this falso view would also be
             there: "That is the world, that is `atta`. I
             shall be after death, everlasting, abiding
             eternal, unchanging and I shall remain as such
             for eternity". The feeling of 'I' and 'mine'
             being absent, the possibility of the false view
             would not be there. So a staunch belief in the
             reality of 'I' and 'mine' is the fulcrum on
             which the illusory image of an eternal soul
             rests.
       (23) `Satkaya` or `Sakkaya` means
            `pancupadanakkhandha` or five aggregates of
            attachment: "`Panca` kho ime...`upadanakkhandha
            sakkayo` vutto `bhagavata` seyyathidam
            `rupupadanakkhandho`, `vedanupadanakkhandho`,
            `sannupadanakkhandho`, `vinnanupadanakkhandho`,
            `samkharupadanakkhandho` (Collavedallasutta,
            Majjhima `Nikaya`, Vol.I,pp.369-70(Nalanda Ed.),
            p.299(PTS)

                                  401 頁

        it, he may even intellectually refute it, but he is
        not yet free from the vestige of this pernicious
        heresy.(24)

              We may refer to passage in the `Kosa`
        literature that helps us to understand more clearly
        the different modes of relationship existing between
        the soul and the five skandhas (Conze, p.33). This
        passage, like the `Samyutta Nikaya` account,
        distinguishes between the twenty bases of grasping at
        the notion of soul. One regards (1-5) the soul as the
        five skandhas, as the flame of a lamp is identical
        with its visual appearance; (6-10) the soul as
        having or possessing the five skandhas, like the
        shadow of a thing;(11-15) the skandhas in the soul,
        as the scent in a flower;(16-20) the soul in the
        skandhas, as the gem in the casket.(25)
        ────────────
       (24) In this connection we may refer to the episode of
            khemaka recorded in the `Samyutta Nikaya`, Vol.Ⅲ,
            pp. 127ff.(PTS Ed.). Some monks ask Khemaka
            whether he sees in the five aggreates of
            attachment any self (`atta`) or anything
            pertaining to self (`attaniya`). Khemaka replies
            in the negative but at the same time admits that
            he is not yet an arhat. "I am not an arhat free
            from all impurities, Oh friends, with regard to
            the five aggregates of attachment. I have a
            feeling 'I am' but I do not clearly see 'This is
            I am'". Then Khemaka explains what he calls 'I
            am' is neither matter, feeling, perception,
            mental formation (`sankhara`) nor consciousness
            nor anything without them. But he has the feeling
            'I am' with regard to the five skadhas, though he
            could not see clearly 'This is I am'. He says it
            is like the smell of a flower, it is neither the
            smell of the petals, nor of the colours, nor of
            the pollens, but the smell of the flower.
            Khemaka further explains that this feeling 'I
            am' disappears when one progresses further, just
            as the chemical smell of a freshly washed cloth
            disappears when it is kept in a box.
       (25) See, E. Conze, Buddhist Thought in India, p.33.
            It is to be noted that the same comparison of
            `atta` with the smell of a flower also occurs in
            the `Samyutta Nikaya` (see, note no. 24). We
            should, however, observe that though Khemaka
            feels 'I am' he does not treasure this feeling;
            he wants to get rid of it as something unreal.
            But to a follower of `Sasvatavada` the feeling
            indicates something real which is the very
            essence of his eternal being. The spiritual
            experience is same in both the cases, though the
            wisdom needed to interpret the experience
            correctly is absent in case of the
            `Sasvatavadins`.

                                  402 頁

              This account of the `Satkayadrsti` acquaints
        us with the most basic form of `atta` heresy.
        `Satkayadrsti` merely postulates a relationship
        between the soul and the five skandhas. It neither
        advocates the eternity of the soul nor holds the
        soul to be co-terminous with the body.
        `Satkayadrsti` is neither `Sasvatavada` nor
        `Ucchedavada`. But the following statement recorded
        in the `Samyutta Nikaya`(26) `ima` kho gahapati
        ditthiyo `sakkayaditthiya` sati honti-shows that the
        `satkaya drsti` is the root cause of all other
        heresies, including the `Sasvatavada` and the
        `Ucchedavada`. A person believing in a soul and
        having desire for existence (`bhava-trsna`)
        willingly believes that the soul survies the body
        and accepts the false view of its permanetnt
        existence (`bhava-drsti`). On the other hand, a
        person thirsting for non-existence
        (`vibhava-trsna`), willingly believes that death is
        the ultimate end of every thing, and comes to
        believe in the false view of non-existence
        (`Vibhavadrsti`) the annihilation of soul after
        death (`Ucchedavada`).(27)

              b)`Sasvatavada`:The account of the
        `Sasvatvada` as given in the `Brahma-jalasutta`(28)
        may be abridged as follows:-

              There are recluses and Brahmanas who accept
        the philosophy of eternalism (`sassatavada`) and
        proclaim that both the soul and the world are
        eternal. And why they do so? Some recluse and
        Brahmana by means of exertion and proper mental
        attention attains to such a cencentration of mind
        that they are able to recall to mind many hundreds
        of thousands of past births. And they think:"There
        ────────────
       (26) `Samyutta`, Vol.Ⅳ,p.287
       (27) Lamotte, Indian Buddhism, pp.35,48,51. In this
            connection we may refer to the
            `Sattasavasutta`, Majjhima `Nikaya`, (Nalanda
            Ed. Vol.Ⅰ,pp.12-13), which also states that it
            is due to ego-centric thoughts (e.g. atthi me
            atta etc.) that such a wrong view arises:"This
            is my self, which speaks and feels, which
            experiences the fruits of good and bad actions
            now here, now there, this self is permanent,
            stable , everlasting, unchanging, remaining the
            same for ever and ever." This false view is
            given the designation of `Sasvatavada` in the
            `Samyutta Nikaya`; "That is the self, that is
            the world (loka). He takes rebirth, he is
            eternal, stable, unchanging- this is the
            eternalist veiw-point." cf, S. PartⅢ,pp. 98-99;
            182
       (28) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol. Ⅰ(PTS Ed. by T.W.Rhys
            Davids)London, 1973, pp.13-14; T.W.Rhys Davids,
            Dialogues of the Buddha, Part Ⅰ, pp.27-28(PTS,
            London, 1977)

                                  403 頁

        I was born of such a name (`evam-namo`), of such a
        lineage and caste (`evam-gotto`,`evam-vanno`).(29)
        My food was such (`evam-aharo`). I was the
        experience of such pleasures and pains
        (`evam-sukha-dukkha-patisamvedi`) and had such a
        span of life (`evam-ayu-pariyanto`). Falling from
        there I was born here."(30) Thus they remember their
        past existences in full detail. And each of them
        says to himself: "sassato `atta` ca loko ca `vanjho
        kutattho esikatthayithito`, te ca `satta sandhavanti
        samsaranti` cavanti upapajjanti, atthi tveva
        sassata-saman ti."(31) T.W.Rhys Davids translates as
        follows: "The soul is eternal; and the world
        giving birth to nothing new, is steadfast as a
        moutain-peak, as a pillar firmly fixed; and that
        though these living creatures transmigrate and pass
        away, fall from one state of existence and spring up
        in another, yet they are (atthi) for ever and ever."
        (32)

              Though this translation tallies with the
        traditional Buddhist explanation, it is difficult to
        accept it, as it raises some problems. From the
        legend we have seen that the living beings in this
        world could only remembers the details of their past
        lives here. And an awareness of an unchangeable 'I'
        (cf. I was born with such a name etc.) links all
        these past lives together and gives rise to the
        notion of an eternal soul (`atta`). The same soul
        was thought to be born again and again as different
        individuals. The `atta` and `satta` are not
        identical. The skandhas are admitted to be different
        in each of these births, though the `atta`
        characterised by the awareness of an 'I' remains
        unchanged.

              The above translation from Rhys Davids of the
        stock description of `Sasvatavada` is not in
        aggreement with the implications of the
        `Sasvatavada` legend. In this translation not only
        the two verbs of motion (`sandhavanti` and
        `samsaranti`) indicating repeated deaths and
        rebirths and so underlining changes are connected
        with the `satta`but also the verb of existence
        (atthi) indicating permanency becomes associated
        with the same `satta`. If we accept this translation
        we have to admit that the `Sasvatavadins` thought
        the concept of eternity to be compatible with the
        ────────────
       (29) in the `Mahapadanasutta` we have `evam-jati` in
            place of evam-vanno. Both the terms mean social
            class or caste. (`Digha Nikaya`, Vol.Ⅱ.p8)
       (30) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol. Ⅰ, p.13(PTS,London, 1975)
       (31) Ibid, p.15
       (32) Dialogue of the buddha, Part Ⅰ. p.28 (PTS,
            London, 1977)

                                  404 頁

        notion of change. The soul's eternity was not at
        variance with its identity with the changeable
        skandhas. But there is no reason to believe that the
        `Sasvatavadins` were so unrealistic as to support
        such an unreasonable view. We have seen that
        according to the `Sasvatavada` the eternal soul
        characterised by a sense of 'I' was different from
        the changing individuals. Moreover, other religious
        groups contemporary of the `Sasvatavadins` were also
        not supporters of such a view. The `Ucchedavadins`
        (33) took the soul to be identical with the skandhas,
        and consistent with this view they held that the soul
        is destroyed together with the body. The
        `Ekaccasassatavadins`(34) believed the `Mahabrahma`
        to be eternal as they did not appear to have known
        that the `Mahabrahma` was also identical with the
        skandhas, created, and subject to death. All the
        religious groups including the `Sasvatavadins` thus
        seem to have held the view that the soul to be
        eternal must have an existence independent of the
        skandhas. So the translation making the `satta`
        eternal cannot be accepted. The only other
        possibility is to take 'atthi' in the sense of a
        singular number and to connect it with 'atta`,
        Then we get the following translation: "The soul
        is eternal; and the world giving birth to nothing
        new, is steadfast as a mountain-peak, as pillar
        firmly fixed; and these living beings move on and
        on, transmigrate, fall from one state of existence,
        rise up in another, but (the soul) exists for
        eternity."

              For our purpose it is, however, important to
        know how the buddhists would understand this
        philosophy. From our discussion of the
        `Satkayadrsti` it is clear that according to the
        Buddhist's interpretation of the false view the soul
        must be either identical with or closely related to
        the Skandhas. The relation is such that the existence
        of a soul apart from the skandhas is unthinkable. The
        changes which the skandhas undergo even during one's
        lifetime are obvious. Moreover the acceptance of the
        repeated deaths and rebirths shows that the skandhas
        do not remain unchanged. In short, according to the
        buddhist interpretation, the `Sasvatavadins`
        admitted the changeable nature of the skandhas,
        accepted the close relationship existing bewteen the
        soul and the skandhas, and yet held the soul to be
        eternal (sassato). This also seems to be the opinion
        of Buddhaghosa (35) as
        ────────────
       (33) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol I, see, p.34; also see, p.12
       (34) See, p.10 ff.

                                  405 頁

        expressed in the `Sumangalavilasini`. But, as already
        shown, Buddhist presentation of the eternalism is
        not the same as the original philosiophy of the
        `Sasvatavadins`. The `Sasvatavadins` themselves
        regarded 'atta' to be independent of body and mind,
        i.e. of the skandhas, to use the Buddhist terminology.
        This seems to be reason why the `Sasvatavadins`
        themselves did not relate the soul to any of the
        skandhas in the stock description of their own
        philosophy. Even the logicians and thinkers (`takki`,
        `vimansi`)(36) among them have nothing to say about
        the relationship existing between the soul and the
        skandhas.

              Whatever may be the case, it is of no consequence
        for our present study that the Buddhist presentation
        of the `atta` of the `Sasvatavadins` does not tally with
        the original concept. What really matters is the
        idea the Buddhists had of such a concept. For when
        they reject a concept of an eternal soul, they do so
        in the light of their own understanding of it. So it
        is important to take note of their idea of the
        `atta` concept which may be described as follows:
        The `atta` is an eternally existent individual soul
        which is either identical with the skandhas or so
        closely related to them as to be dependent on them
        for its very existence. It neither attains
        liberation nor gets annihilated.

              c)`Ekaccasassatavada`:A concept of `atta`
        different from that of the eternalists has been
        recorded in the `Brahmajalasutta` of the
        `Digha-Nikaya`.(37) This is the concept of an
        eternal soul unique to the `Mahabrahma` as held by
        the followers of the `Ekaccasassatavada`. The Buddha
        in order to explain the origin of the
        `Ekaccasassatavada` relates the following legend
        about the past lives of the upholders of this
        philosophy:

              When the world system dissolves the beings are
        reborn in the `Abhassara` world. They are made of
        mind. Now the world system begins to come into
        exitence and an empty `Braham-vimana`(Brahma-palace)
        appears. One of the beings at the end of merits or
        span of life falls from the `Abhassara` world and is
        reborn in the Brahma-palace. There he lives, made of
        mind (manomayo), feeding on joy (`piti-bhakkho`),
        radiating light. etc. and thus does remain there for
        a
        ────────────
       (35) `Sumangalavilasini`, Vol. I, p.105(PTS,London,
            1968)
       (36) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol. I, p.16
       (37) Ibid. pp.17-19;Dialogues of the Buddha, Part I,
            pp.30-32

                                  406 頁

        long time. And he feels lonely and longs for
        companions. Just then some beings die in the
        `Abhassara` world and are born in the Brahma-palace.
        They are just like the being who was first born. As
        these beings were born after he desired for company,
        he thought himself to be `Brahma Mahabrahma`,
        Creator, Father of all that are and are to be. And
        the other beings also thought that they have been
        created by `Mahabrahma`. Their lives are of shorter
        duration than that of `Mahabrahma`. They die in the
        Brahma-palace and are reborn here in this world.
        Here one of them leads a religious life and can
        remember his past existence in the Brahma-palace,
        but not beyond that. He thinks of `Mahabrahma` as
        creator permanent, fixed, eternal, of a nature which
        is not subject to transformation (nicco, dhuvo,
        sassato, `aviparinamadhammo`) while he regards
        himself and other beings as created by `Mahabrahma`,
        impermanent, not fixed, eternal, and having the
        nature of dying (`ancica`, `addhuva`, `appayuka`,
        `cavanadhamma`).

              The last part of the above account seems to be
        a stock description which formed a part of the
        original philosophy of the `Ekaccasassatavadins`.
        According to their philosophy only the uncreated is
        eternal while the created is impermanent. Only
        `Mahabrahma` is eternal and the other beings are
        impermanent. The information that `Mahabrahma` was
        made of mind were most probably not included in
        their philosophy, for it is not mentioned in the
        utterance of him who remembers his past existence.
        Otherwise we have to assume that according to the
        `Ekaccasassatavadins` mind can be both created and
        uncreated. So it appears that this extra bit of
        information has been added in accordance with the
        Buddhis dogma.  Thus as per the understandings of
        the Buddhists, the followers of the
        `Ekaccasassatvada` believed in an eternal soul only
        in case of `mahabrahma` and this soul was made of
        mind, uncreated and immortal.

              Two other groups of the `Ekaccasassatavadins`
        (38) believed in many eternal individual souls. But
        the eternity is not absolute in these cases; it may
        be lost either due to the lack of self-controll or
        due to envy. The fourth group of the
        `Ekaccasassatavadins`(39) were comprised of the
        logicians and the thinkers who concluded by
        reasoning that there are two souls, one impermanent
        and the other
        ────────────
       (38) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol. I, pp.19-21
       (39) Ibid, p.21

                                  407 頁

        permanent. The soul consisting of ear, nose tongue
        and body is impermanent, not fixed, not eternal and
        having the changeable nature. But the soul which is
        thought or mind or consciousness (cittan ti va mano
        ti va `vinnaran` ti va ) is permanent, eternal etc.

              d)`Ucchedavada`: The seven groups of
        `Ucchedavadins`(40) identified an individual soul
        variously with physical body, or sensual desire, or
        mind, or infinite space, or infinite consciousness,
        or nothingness, or neither perception nor not
        perception. The first group believed in one soul
        made of gross matter while the other groups believed
        in more than one souls. And all these groups upheld
        the doctrine that the soul is annihilated with the
        destruction of the body. It appears that even before
        the Buddhists the `Ucchedavadins` denied the belief
        in an eternal individual soul (`atta`) which was
        identical with one of the skandhas. Therefore this
        philosophy came to be known as the doctrine of
        `niratta`.

              So far we have discussed the `Satkayadrsti`,
        `Sasvatavada`, `Ekaccasasvatavada` and the
        `Ucchedavada`, and these are the only dominant
        heresies regarding `atta` and relevant to our study
        that have been recorded in the `Agamas` and
        `Nikayas`.(41) Presumably these were the four main
        type of heresies that attracted the attention of the
        Buddha and the early Buddhists. It is obvious that
        the `atta` concepts discussed in the `Ucchedavada`
        and `Satkayadrsti` can in no way be connected with
        the problem of `atta's` identity with the
        `Upanisadic Atman`. It is only the `Sasvatavada` and
        `Ekaccasassatavada` concept that deserves to be
        considered in this connection.

              In course of our discussion we have noted the
        following characteristics of an eternal soul as
        envisaged by the followers of the `Sasvatavada` and
        `Ekaccasassatavada`. The first group of
        `Ekaccasassatavada` believed that only the
        ────────────
       (40) Ibid, pp.34-35
       (41) I have not mentioned the other `atta` heresies
            described in the `Brahmajalasutta`, as they are
            not radically different from what we have
            discussed in the present article. All these
            heresies are also based on the `Satkayadrsti`
            and so share the characteristics of the
            `Satkayadrsti`. These heresies must also be
            partially similar to the `Sasvatavadins or the
            `Ekaccasassatavadins`. I could not trace any
            other sutta devoted to the rejection of any of
            these heresies. The Buddhists themselves, it
            seems , did not think it necessary to discuss
            these false views separately and elaborately.

                                  408 頁

        soul of `Mahabrahma`, who is uncreated, is eternal.
        But the `Sasvatavada` and the other groups of
        `Ekaccasassatavada` recognise numerous, eternal,
        individual souls who are either identical with the
        skandhas or so closely related to them as to be
        dependent on them for their very existence. The
        second and third groups of the `Ekaccasassatavadins`,
        however, are of the opinion that the eternity is not
        absolute, for the beings die if they indulge in
        sensual pleasures or are afflicted with jealousy. The
        first type of `Ekaccasassatavada` explicitly states
        that the souls, including that of the `Mahabrahma`,
        are made of mind. This view seems to have been
        accepted by the second and third groups of the
        `Ekaccasassatavadins` who made the eternity of the
        individual souls dependent on the purity of mind.
        According to the fourth group of the
        `Ekaccasassatavadins` which consists of the logicians
        and the thinkers, the individual soul is identical
        with citta or manas or `vijnana`. Thus we find that
        the `Ekaccasassatavada` concept of soul belonged to
        the sphere of mind and at least in most cases could
        not rise beyond the `Rupaloka`. Moreover the eternal
        souls are confined within space and time and are
        characterised by the subject-object split.

              The `Upanisadic Atman`, on the other hand, is
        not an individual soul. The `Atman` is the supreme
        reality, the only Being that is beyond speech, beyond
        the reach of mind and the notion of space. And such
        an ` Atman can by no strech of imagination be equated
        with any of the skandhas. In short, the sassato
        `atta` of the Buddhist scriptures and the `Atman` of
        the Upanisads are two diametrically opposing points
        of view.

              So long we have discussed scriptural materials
        which are more or less descriptive in nature. Now we
        pay attention to a more critical type of `Agama
        Nikaya` passages which acquaint us with the reasons
        for the rejection of different types of `atta`
        heresies, and thereby provide us with some extra
        details regarding these heresies.

                               Ⅳ
              We have seen that four kinds of relationship
        between the `atta` and the skandhas were recognised.
        Out of these only one type of relationship viz. that
        of identity between the `atta` and the skandhas,
        finds prominent mention in the `Nikayas` and the
        `Agamas`. This appears to have been the dominant
        heresy at the

                                  409 頁

        time of the Buddha. Only in a few cases the early
        buddhist canon takes note of other types of
        relationship, viz. `atta` has skandhaka or `atta` is
        not a particular type of skandhaka. Again the nature
        and contents of such a criticism of `atta` heresy
        vary depending on the type of persons for whom it
        was meant. The discourses which are held for the
        benefit of the Buddhist monks are quite different
        from those meant for non-Buddhist asceties.

              with these preliminary remarks we will now
        proceed to arrange the relevant materials according
        to the type of heresies criticised and the type of
        persons addressed.

        A:Criticism of heresies meant for the Buddhist
           monks
              Ⅰ)Rejection of `Satkayadrsti`:The `samyutta`
        passage referred to above is a plain form of
        instruction discarding the heresy of `Satkayadrsti`.
        The Buddha points out that some recluses and
        Brahmans by erroneous observations of the skandhas
        give rise to the false notion of a soul, but those
        who are wise never make this mistake. Here the talk
        is about the mere existence of a soul with reference
        to the skandhas, and not the eternity or
        impermanence of soul. It is apparent that the Buddha
        is rejecting the `Satkayadrsti`. The Buddha does not
        find it necessary to offer any extra argument in
        favour of his view, as he addresses his own
        disciples who have absolute faith in his wisdom.

              Ⅱ)Criticism of `Sasvatavada`: In the account
        of the `Brahmajalasutta` which we have already
        discussed, the Buddha gives critical description of
        the heresy of `Sasvatavada` in the form of a legend.
        He points out that some recluses and Brahmanas
        believe in eternal individual soul for they can
        remember their past lives in this world. The sutta
        implies that the memory of the past lives is genuine
        though the interpretation of such experiences is
        wrong. In this passage no logical argument is
        advanced justifying the rejection of this heresy. It
        will, however, be clear later from our discussion of
        another passage from the same sutta that the Buddha
        rejects this view on the basis of his more extensive
        knowledge and higher knowledge.

              Ⅲ)Criticism of `Ekaccasassatavada`:Like the
        legend about the `Sasvatavada`, the legend
        concerning the `Ekaccasassatavada` in the
        `Brahmajalasutta` implicitly contains the criticism
        of the concept of an eternal soul. The legend states
        that

                                  410 頁

        the beings who died in the `Brahma` world were born
        in this world. While in this world they could
        remember their past birth in the `Brahma-vimana`,
        but had no knowledge of their still earlier birth in
        the `Abhassara` world, nor could they know that
        `Mahabrahma` is also subject to death. This legend
        suggests that the incomplete experience coupled with
        imperfect knowledge led these beings to interpret
        wrongly their genuine spiritual experiences.
        Consequently they came to believe in the false
        notion of an eternal `Mahabrahma` who is made of
        mind. So the Buddha is here criticising
        `Ekaccasassatavada` on the basis of his more
        extensive knowledge.

              Ⅳ)Criticism of heresies in general: There is
        no legend criticising the `Ucchedavada`. This is
        because the `Ucchedavada` tradition most probably
        did not record any legend justifying this
        philosophy. The `Ucchedavada` philosophy only
        recognised the present life and denied the existence
        of any life before birth and after death. So there
        was no scope for the development of any such legend.

              In the `Brahmajalasutta`, however, we come
        across a general criticism of all the false views
        noted in this sutta.(42) Here the criticism is based
        on the more extensive knowledge and higher knowledge
        of the Buddha. The passage in question states that
        the Buddha knows of all these false views and also
        knows of into what sort of future existences fall
        those who grasp at and become attached to such
        views. Knowing this and knowing (other) higher
        things (`tan` ca ` Tathagato pajanati`, tato ca
        `uttaritaram pajanati`) the `Tathagata` does not get
        involved, he knows about extinction; and having
        truly known the rising and passing away of
        sensations (`vedananam samudayan` ca `atthamgaman`
        ca), their taste, danger, their not being the refuge,
        `Tathagata`, due to the non-attachment, is free
        (vimutto).

              These are those other things, profound,
        difficult, to understand......not to be grasped at by
        mere logic, which `Tathagata` having himself realised
        and seen face to face, has set forth."

              The higher knowledge which is profound and
        beyond logic is different from the knowledge of
        future existences and past lives of the beings. The
        phrase- "Knowing this and knowing (other) higher
        things" -clearly shows that two different types of
        knowledge are referred to. The higher knowledge
        refers to the
        ────────────
        (42) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol.I,pp.16-17,21-22,24,28,29
             etc.

                                  411 頁

        rising and passing away of `vadana` (sensation or
        feeling), i.e. the knowledge of the
        `paticcasamuppada` which only the Buddha possessed.
        That the statement reggarding `'vedana'` refers to
        the truth of the dependent origination is confirmed
        by another passage of the same sutta (D. 1.3.71). All
        the false views are rejected because they are
        contradicated by the law of dependent origination. Of
        all the links of the `Paticcasamuppada`, `Vedana` is
        specially mentioned, for the awareness of 'I' is
        directily dependent on `vedana`.

              In corroboration of the the conclusion reached
        above we may take note of another sutta where the
        rejection of a false view on the basis of
        `paticcasamuppada` is explicitly mentioned.

              Ⅴ)Rejection of the `Ekaccasassatavada`: The
        Buddha in his instruction to his disciple
        `Kevattaputto Sati` is rejecting the
        `Ekaccasassatavada` on the basis of
        `paticcasamuppada`. (43) `Sati` gave out that it is
        the self-same `vijnana` that passes from one
        existence to another. Here `Sati` is speaking in
        favour of `Sasvatavada`. This statement is
        elaborated in the `Papancasudani`(44) to bring out
        its full significance:"That which speaks,
        experiences now here now there, the fruits of his
        good and evil actions is that consciousness
        (`vijnana`) that I am speaking about.' The same
        `vijnana` is enjoying the fruits of his actions.
        This is the same as preaching `Sasvatavada` as it
        will be clear from a passage of the `Sabbasavasutta`
        of the Majjhima `Nikaya` and a passage from the
        `Samyutta Nikaya`. The Majjhima passage runs thus
        (45):Atha va pana assa evam `ditthi` hoti:yo me
        ayam `atta` vado vedeyya tatra tatra
        kalyanapapakanam `vipakam patisamvedeti` so kho pana
        me ayam `atta` nicco dhuvo sassato aviparinamodhammo
        sassatisamam tath'eva thassati' 'Or a wrong view
        occurs to him thus:the soul of mine that speaks,
        experiences now here and now there the fruits of his
        good and evil actions is indeed that soul of mine
        that is permanent, stable, not subject to change,
        that will stand firm for eternity.' The `Samyutta`
        passage (46) states: One and the same person both
        acts and
        ────────────
        (43) M.I, `Mahatanhasankhayasutta`, pp.256ff. idam
             `vinnanam sandhavanti`, `samsaranti anannam`.
             ibid.p.256.
        (44) `Papancasudam`,Vol.Ⅱ,p.305(PTS,London, 1979)
        (45) Majjhima, Vol.Ⅰ,p.8(PTS,London, 1976)
        (46) `Samyutta Nikaya`, Vol.Ⅱ,p.20

                                  412 頁

        experiences (the results)- this Kassapa which you
        called at first 'suffering self-wrought' ammounts to
        the Eternalist theory. (47)

              It is also to be noted that `Sati` is
        identifying the eternal soul with the `vijnana`
        only. This reminds us of the view of the logicians
        among the `Ekaccasassatavadins` who held that
        indriya etc. are impermanent while the citta
        (thought), or manas (mind), or `vijnana`
        (consciousness) is eternal. So the eternalism which
        `Sati` is preaching actually ammounts to the
        `Ekaccasassatavada` of the logicians. To reject this
        view the Buddha refer to the law of dependent
        origination (`paticcasamuppada`). The Buddha
        condemned the view of `Sati` and corrected him by
        pointing out that `vijnana` can only originate
        through cause and conditions (`annatra paccaya`
        na'tthi `vinnanassa` sambhavo ti)(48) and so cannot
        be eternal.

              In the preceding pages we have dealt with such
        criticisms of the false views regarding `atta` as
        were meant for the loyal disciples of the Buddha.
        For his disciples the unquestionable veracity of
        these criticisms ultimately rests on their
        unflagging faith in the claim of the Buddha to the
        more extensive and higher types of knowledge. It was
        not necessary for the Buddha to analyse critically
        the different heresies in order to expose the flaws
        in them, or to adduce extra reasons to justify their
        rejection. The approach, however, changes when the
        discourses are meant for the non-Buddhist ascetics.

        B:Criticism of heresies meant for non-Buddhist
           ascetics
              Ⅰ)Rejection of `Sasvatavada`:(49) The
        `Anatta-lakkhana` -sutta of the `Samyutta Nikaya` (
        ⅢⅩⅩⅡ, 59)(50) while giving a clear exposition of
        the `anatta` doctrine,
        ────────────
        (47) Kindred Sayings, Vol.Ⅱ,p.16(PTS,London, 1982)
        (48) Majjhima, Vol.Ⅰ,p.259. It appears that `Sati`
             misunderstood the Buddhist doctrine of rebirth.
             It is said in the `Samyutta Nikaya` (Ⅰ,122;
             Ⅱ,67,103) that is only when `vinnana` obtains
             a footing on something (`arammana`) that there
             is the possiblity of the birth of a being, and
             not otherwise, and the moment the `vinnana`
             ceases (cuti), one is regarded as dead. Also
             see, Nalinaksha dutt, Early Monastic Buddhism,
             Vol.Ⅰ,P.255 (Calcutta, 1941).
        (49) `Samyutta`, Vol.Ⅱ,pp.66-68(PTS.London, 1960);
             Vinaya, Vol.Ⅰ,P.13-14(PTS, London, 1964)

                                  413 頁

        adduces reasons for the denial of `atta` in the
        following manner: Form (`rupa`) is not soul
        (`atta`). If it were , this form could not turn
        oppressive, and with regard to form it would be
        possible to achieve the intention that "let my body
        be thus, let my body be not thus". And so with
        `vedana`, `sanna`, `samkhara`, and `vinnana`. "What
        do you think, is form permanent or impermenet?" "It
        is impermanet, Oh Lord". "But is the impermanent ill
        (dukkha) or ease (sukha)?" "It is ill, Oh Lord".
        "But is it fitting to consider that which is
        impermanent linked to suffering, doomed to reversal
        as 'this is mine, I am this, this is my soul'". "No,
        indeed, Oh lord". And so for `vedana`, `sanna` ect.
        Therefore whatever form there is, past or future,
        inner or outer, gross or subtle, low or exalted,
        near or far away, would be seen by right wisdom as
        it really is, i.e. "all this form is not really mine,
        I am not really this, this is not my soul (`atta`)."
        And so `vedana`, `sanna` etc. Seeing this the
        well-disciplined holy disciple become disgusted with
        the skandhas."

              From a careful study of the passage quoted
        above the concept of the `atta` rejected here clearly
        emerges. The `rupa` and other skandhas cannot be
        `atta` for they turn oppressive and cannnot be
        changed according to one's liking. So it follows that
        te `atta` or the individual soul enjoys complete
        self-mastery and remains ever happy. Moreover the
        five skandhas are not `atta` for they are impermanent
        and subject to change and suffering. This shows that
        the `atta` concept rejected here was believed to be
        identical with the skandhas, permanent, changeless,
        happy and characterised by an awareness of an 'I' and
        'mine'. So the concept of `atta` which emerges wholly
        conforms to the `Sasvatavada`.

              Two opposing trends of thought are discernible
        in this sutta. One represent the viewpoint of the
        `Sasvatavada` as presented above. The other trend
        shows the Buddha's acceptance of the notion of I and
        mine as a basis for further argumentation in order to
        disprove the soul's identity with the skandhas. The
        line of reasoning, partly explicit and partly
        implicit, may be presented thus: the idea of 'I' and
        'mine' is the characteristic feature of atta and
        implies complete self-mastery of oneself. What one
        refers to as 'I' and 'mine' must be its own master.
        Moreover the individual soul is permanent. But the
        body (`rupa`) is beyond one's control.
        ────────────
        (50) `Digha Nikaya`, Vol.Ⅰ,pp.179,182 ff.;Dialogues
             of the Buddha, Part Ⅰ, p.246ff. Also see,
             A.K.Warder, Indian Buddhism (Motilal Banarasidas,
             Delhi, 1991) pp.124ff.


                                  414 頁


        It grows, becomes old and ultimately dies without
        anybody being able to do anything to arrest this
        process. In short this philosophy upholds the
        self-mastery and permanency of an individual soul
        but advocates in the same breath the identity of the
        soul with the five skandhas which are impermanent
        and lack self-mastery. Thus it is clear that the
        viewpoint of the `Sasvatavadins` suffers from
        internal contradiction and cannot be accepted.

              It should be noted that the Buddha did not
        criticise this philosophy on the basis of any
        Buddhist doctrine. The impermanence of body etc, is
        a matter of common experience and no higher philophy
        is needed to prove it. The Buddha neither referred
        to the skandhas constituting a being nor to the law
        of `paticcasamuppada` in order to deny the existence
        of a permanent ego-centric entity. Rather he made
        use of the notion of 'I' which is taken to be the
        tell-tale sign of an individual soul to refute the
        `Sasvatavada`. This approach appears to be all the
        more intriguing as the Buddha is preaching to his
        own disciples, and not to the non-Buddhist ascetics.
        And from the dialogue between the Buddha and his
        disciples it is obvious that his disciples has not
        turned into supporters of this false view, but had
        remained faithful to his teachings. Moreover it
        would be preposterous to hold that the Buddha
        actually supported the existence of a permanent
        individual soul, although he denied its identity
        with the five skandhas. What, then, is the reason
        for this particular mode of preaching? We can
        reasonably surmise that he was instructing his
        disciples how to meet the challenges of such an
        erroneous view. The inadvisability of trying to
        discard this false view by referring to the Buddhist
        doctrine is obvious, for the non-Buddhists cannot be
        expected to have any faith in the teachings of the
        Buddha. So the Buddha was teaching his disciples how
        such false doctrines could be successfully countered
        even while basing one's argumants on such articles
        of faith as formig an integral part of the
        philosophy they were criticising. He was trying to
        show how the logical implications of one aspect of
        this false doctrine would render null and void
        another aspect of the same doctrine. In other words
        the Buddha was teaching his disciples to expose the
        contradictions inherent in the doctrines of the
        `Sasvatavadins` in such a way that even the
        upholdres of this philosophy would be forced to
        admit the justification of the criticism. In the
        `Anatta-lakkhana-sutta` the point which the Buddha
        drives home is that the logical implications of the
        notion of 'I'

                                  415 頁

        which were acceptable to the protagonists of this
        philosophy, would contradict the other part of the
        philosophy, viz. the identity of the individual soul
        with the skandhas. It is also clear that the sutta
        was ultimately meant for the `Sasvatavadins`
        themselves.

              Ⅱ)a) The `Potthapadasutta` and the rejection
        of `Satkayadrsti`: this sutta starts with a
        discussion of the rising and the cessation of
        perception (`sanna` or `abhisanna`) and then follows
        it up with a judgement about the problem of identity
        between the soul and perception. We will just have a
        glimpse of the discussion as it will help us to
        understand the nature of perception. The Buddha gave
        a gradual discoures on the higher and higher stages
        of perception leading to the summit of perception
        (`sannaggam`) and then to the cessation of
        perception (nirodha). Except the final stage, at
        every other stage a perception of a lower type is
        replaced by a perception of a higher type. The
        Buddha showed that a certain type of perception
        arose due to a certain type of thinking, a certain
        type of mental training. When the thinking ceased,
        the perception also ceased. With the cessation of
        all thoughts, the possibility of the rising of any
        new perception comes to an end.

              Next `Potthapada` raises the question of a
        soul. "Is perception the soul of a man, Sir, or is
        perception one thing and soul another?" The Buddha
        asked, "What, now, `Potthapads`, do you assume a
        soul?" "I presume a gross soul Sir, material, made
        of four great elements, feeding on solid food". "Yet
        if your soul were gross, `Potthapada`, material,
        made of four gross elements feeding on solid food,
        in that case for you perception would be one thing,
        soul another. Just let this gross soul be,
        `Potthapada`, for then a man's perception occurs as
        one thing, ceases as another thing". `Potthapada`
        next proposes to assume a mental soul, with perfect
        faculties, complete in its faculties. The Buddha's
        objection remains the same: perception would then
        occur as one thing but cease as another thing.
        Lastly `Pottapada` proposes an immaterial soul,
        consisting of perception. the objection of the
        Buddha is still the same.

              The denial of the identity between the soul
        and perception is based on the following pattern of
        reasoning. If the soul is material like body, then
        the soul cannot be identical with perception. For in
        that case the perception would be rising as one
        thing and ceasing as another. It means that as long
        as the perception is in existence, it can be assumed
        to be soul (as body). But when it ceases to be, it

                                  416 頁

        can no longer be equated with the soul, for the
        living material soul would be still in existence.
        Hence the statement about the perception as rising
        as one and ceasing as another. This reasoning also
        holds good while showing the difference between the
        perception and soul as mind, for the cessation of a
        particular perception does not mean the annihilation
        of mind. But this type of reasoning is not valid
        when one assumes the soul to be made of perception.
        In this case the cessation of perception will
        automatically mean the annihilation of soul, and
        consequently the argument that the perception ceases
        as another is no longer tenable. This part of the
        discussion appears to be a later mechanical
        addition.

              Whatever may be the case, it is obvious that
        `Potthapada` is equating `atta` with a a skandhaka.
        In his query about the identity of the soul with
        perception as well as in his suggestion that the
        soul may be made of four gross elements, or of mind,
        or of perception, `Potthapada` is equating soul with
        one of the skandhakas. He is not concerned about the
        eternity of the soul or otherwise. In other words we
        are dealing here with the `Satkayadrsti`, the root
        cause of all other false views.

              In rejecting the `Satkayadrsti` the Buddha is
        not denying the existence of `atta` on the basis of
        `paticcasamuppada` as he did while instructing his
        own disciples. He is even accepting-for the sake of
        argument, or we may say as a skillful means-
        `Potthapada's` point of view regarding the existence
        of soul or the constitution of soul, and then
        rejecting the suggested identity by exposing the
        logical inconsistencies involved in the suggestion.
        He is showing that the acceptance of the view that
        the soul is made of mind or four gross elements
        contradicts the other aspect of the suggestion, viz.
        soul is identical with perception.

                 b)`Mahanidanasutta` and the rejection of a
        diiierent type of `Satkayadrsti`(51)

              `Mahanidanasutta`(52) rejects a new type of
        `Satkayadrsti` which may be formulated as soul
        possessing feelings. The relevant passage is given
        below:"Herein, again, `Aanada`, to him who affirms
        :'Nay, my soul is not feeling, nor is it non-
        ────────────
        (51) For Sanskrit parallels to different `atta`
             concepts discussed in the `Mahanidanasutta`,
             see, `Nidanasamyukta`, C.B.Tripathi, Deutsche
             Akademie der Wissenschaften Zu Berlin, IO,
             1962.
        (52) `Digha nikaya`, Vol.Ⅱ,ⅩⅤ.31,p.67(PTS London,
             1982), Dialogues of the Buddha PartⅡ,p.64(Pts,
             London, 1977)

                                  417 頁

        -sentient; my soul has feelings, it has the
        property of sentience'─answer should be made:'My
        friend, were feelings of every kind to cease
        absolutely, then there being, owing to cessation
        thereof, no feeling whatever, could one then say:
        -"I myself am'?"

              'No, lord, one could not.'

              'Wherefore, `Ananda`, it follows that this
        aspect:-`Nay, my soul is not feel feeling, nor is
        it non-sentient; my soul has feelings, it has the
        property of sentience'-does not commend itself".

              Here the Buddha is teaching `Ananda` how to
        refute the heresy of `Satakayadrsti`. The view that
        the soul is not feeling, but possesses feelings
        shows that the feeling is not intrinsic to `atta`
        but external to it. It, therefore, follows that the
        presence or absence of feeling should not at all
        affect the basic nature of soul. But, as the Buddha
        points out, our daily experience shows that in the
        absence of all feelings there cannot be any
        I-awareness which is the very essence of `atta`. So
        the feeling is not external to soul; soul cannot be
        regarded as having feelings. The accepted idea that
        `atta` essentially means I-awareness goes against
        the view that `atta` has feelings.

              The `atta` heresy under discussion is
        concerned with the relationship existing between the
        soul and the skandhakas, and so falls under the
        category of `satkayadrsti`.

              It is by way of expediency that the Buddha
        accepts I-awareness as the very core of an assumed
        `atta` and thereby shows that the present heresy
        suffers from internal contradiction. It is also to
        be noted that the Buddha's instructions, though
        addressed to `Ananda`, is ultimately meant for the
        non-Buddhist ascetics.

              Ⅲ) The `Mahanidanasutta` and the rejection of
        the `Ekaccasassatavada`

              The `Mahanidanasutta`(53) also contains
        passages rejecting the heresy that the soul is
        feeling. The relevant part of the sutta runs as
        follows:-"Herein,`Ananda`, to him who affirms' My
        soul is feeling'-answer should be thus made:-' My
        friend, feelings is of three kinds. There is happy
        feeling, painful feeling, and neutral feeling. Of
        these three feelings, look you, which do you
        consider your soul is?'
        ────────────
        (53) Dialogues of the Buddha, PartⅡ,pp.63-64;
             `Digha Nikaya`, Vol.Ⅱ,ⅩⅤ.28;29,pp.66-67

                                  418 頁

              'When you feel a happy feeling you do not feel
        a painful feeling or a neutral feeling, you feel
        just a happy feeling. And when you feel a painful
        feeling, you do not feel a happy feeling or a
        neutral feeling, but just a painful feeling. And
        when you feel a neutral feeling, you do not feel a
        happy feeling or a painful feeling; you feel just a
        neutral feeling.'

              "Moreover, `Ananda`, happy feeling is
        impermanent, conditioned (`sankhata`), the result of
        cause or causes, liable to perish, to pass away, to
        become extinct, to cease. So too the painful
        feeling. So too is neutral feeling. If when
        experiencing a happy feeling one thinks -'this is my
        soul' -when that same happy feeling ceases, one will
        also think -'my soul has departed' -So too when the
        feeling is painful or neutral. Thus he who say -'My
        soul is feeling' -regards, as his soul something
        which, in this present life, is impermanent, is
        blended of happiness and pain, and is liable to
        begin and end. Wherefore, `Ananda`, it follows that
        this aspect -'My soul is feeling' -does not commend
        itself."

              The passage in question rejects the view that
        the individual soul is feeling. The daily experience
        of people shows that the feeling is impermanent, a
        blending of happiness and pain, and subject to
        origination and destruction. This characterisation
        of feeling will be, in the main, also acceptable to
        the `Ekaccasassatavadins`, for they, as we have
        already noted, accepted the idea that the created is
        impermanent. The feeling so characterised is
        different from soul. The soul thus appears to be
        permanent, beyond origination and destruction, and
        experiencing unmixed happiness. It is identical with
        one of the skandhas.

              This concept of `atta` is, in all its
        essential features, identical with that held by the
        logicians among the `Ekaccasassadtavadins` who also
        believed the individual soul to be eternal, and
        identical with one of the skandhas belonging to the
        sphere of mind.

              It is to be noted that the Buddha is denying
        the `Ekaccasassatavada` not on the strength of the
        law of `paticcasamuppada` or any other Buddhist
        dogma. It is obviously becasue his invoking of the
        higher knowledge would cut no ice with the
        non-Buddhists. He is, on the other hand, showing
        that the philosophy under criticism suffers from
        internal contradiction, and hence untenable. He
        shows that the `Ekaccasassatavada` concept of
        feeling is diametrically opposed to the
        `Ekaccasassatavada` concept of soul, and so the
        view that the soul is identical with feeling


                                  419 頁

        is to be discarded.

              The `Mahanidanasutta` passage suports our
        conclusion that the Buddha also taught his disciples
        how to defeat the upholders of the `atta` heresy in
        debate. Here the Buddha is teaching `Ananda` how to
        refute the view of the `Ekaccasassatavadins`. In
        other words his teaching is ultimately meant for the
        followers of the `Ekaccasassatavada`.

              Ⅳ) The `mahanidanasutta` rejects an atypical
        `atta` heresy:In the `Mahanidanasutta`(54) we come
        across a heresy which does not conform to any of the
        types mentioned before. The relevant passage
        recording a negative formulation the heresy is
        given below:-
              "Herein, `Ananda`, to him who affirms:'Nay,
              my soul is not feeling, my soul is not
              sentient'-answer should thus be given:'My
              friend, where there is no feeling of anything,
              can you there say:'I am?' 'You cannot,
              Lord.' 'Wherefore, `Ananda`, it follows that
              this aspect:'Nay, my soul is not feeling, my
              soul is not sentient'-does not commend
              itself."

              The view that the individual soul is not
        feeling and sentient is rejected because there
        cannot be any awareness of 'I' without feeling and
        sentience. Hence there cannot be any soul without
        feeling and sentience. Here the criticism is based
        on the assumption of 'I-awareness' as the essence of
        te individual soul. The proposition admits of the
        existence of an individual soul, asserts the soul's
        difference from feeling and sentience, and is silent
        about the question whether the individual soul is
        eternal or not. This is a new type of `atta` heresy
        which is neither `Sasvatavada` nor `Ucchedavada`.
        Strictly speaking this negative formulation is not
        even an illustration of `Satkayardrstti`, as it
        denies, instead of affirming, the relationship
        existing between the soul and the skandhas.

              Against our contention one may argue that the
        `formulation-atta` is not feeling - was merely used
        to imply that the soul is identical with some other
        skandha. In this case this implication should be
        treated as the main proposition, which is different
        from the given proposition. If this were so, the
        Buddhist criticism
        ────────────
        (54) Dialogues, Part Ⅱ,p.64; `Digha Nikaya` Vol.
            Ⅱ,ⅩⅤ.30,p.67

                                  420 頁

        would have been directed against a proposition
        asserting the identity of soul with skandhaka and
        not against the formulation of the soul not being
        feeling. But as this is not the case, we have to
        take the given proposition as the main proposition.

              Though the negative formulation states that
        the individual soul is not the same as feeling, it
        should not be interpreted to mean that the soul is
        not connected with any of the five skandhas. For the
        `Samyutta Nikaya` passage quoted above shows that
        the negative formulation of this type is also the
        result of the `Satkayarsti`.

              To sum up, the `atta` concepts held by the
        followers of the `Sasvatavada`, `Ekaccasassatavada`,
        `Ucchedavada`, and `Satkayadrstti` mainly have been
        criticised and rejected in the `Nikayas` and
        `Agamas`. None of these concepts are identical with
        the `Upanisadic Atman-Brahman`.

              Except the `Ucchedavada`, all other concepts
        regarding `atta` have been criticised in two
        defferent ways. When the criticisms rejecting the
        `atta` heresies were addressed to his own disciples,
        the Buddha referred to his more extensive knowledge
        that could see farther into the past and future
        lives of the beings, and his superior knowledge of
        the law dependent origination (`Paticcasamuppada`).
        But when the  criticisms were meant for the
        non-Buddhist ascetics all references to these two
        types of knowledge were avoided. The Buddha by way
        of expediency makes use of a part of the opponent's
        proposition for the sake of further argumentation,
        and thereby lays bare the internal contradictions
        involved in the proposition. This method of reductio
        ad absurdum which the Buddha introduced, was later
        applied by `Nagarjuna` with great success.

              The `Ucchedavada` was criticised only on the
        basis of the Buddha's extensive knowledge and
        superior knowledge but not on logical grounds, as
        the `Ucchedavada philosophy does not suffer from any
        logical inconsistencies.

                             Ⅴ

              We have shown that the early Buddhist
        scripture rejected any notion of `atta` which was
        either identical with the skandhas or dependent on
        them for its very existence. The Buddha specially
        took great pains to discard the `Sasvatavadins` and
        the `Ucchedavadins` who preached the philosophy of
        `atta` and `niratta` respectively. The Buddhists
        were aware of this fact and gave expression to it in

                                  421 頁

        canonical and non-canonical texts. We will cite a
        few quotations from the Buddhist texts in support of
        our view. In the `Dutthatthakasutta`(NO.8) of the
        `Suttanipata` we read the following verse;(55)
              "attam nirattam na hi tassa `atthi` adhosi se
              ` ditthimidha sabba`"

              Here the belief in `atta` and `niratta` are
        counted among the false views (`ditthi`) which a
        follower of the Buddha has given up. Again the
        following two verses from Lalitavistara(56) and
        `Madhyamikakarika`(57) while confirming the Buddhist
        rejection of both `atta` and `niratta` give some
        extra information regarding these heresies:
              Ⅰ)`astinastivinirumktamatmyanairatmyavarjitam
                 prakrtya jatinirdesam dharmacakram
                 ihocyate`.
              Ⅱ)`astiti sasvatagraho nastityucchedadarsanam
                  tasmadastivanastitve nasriyeta vicaksana`.

              From the verses quoted above it is evident
        that the existence of an eternal indireidual soul
        (`atta`) was preached in the philosophy of the
        `Sasvatavada` and term 'asti' in its vocabulary did
        not convey the ordinary meaning of mere existence
        but acquired the special sense of eternal existence.
        On the other hand the `Ucchedavada` which preached
        the philosophy of `niratta` (`nairatmya`), coined
        the term'nasti' to signify simultaneous annihilation
        of the temporarily existing `atta` and the physical
        body. It is in these special senses that the Pali
        Buddhist texts use these two terms 'asti' and
        'nasti' while recording the dialogues between the
        Buddha and the non-Buddhist ascetics. Any lack of
        awareness of the special imports of 'asti' and
        `'nasti'` may result in drawing wrong conclusions
        from such dialogues.

              As the ego-centricity and absolute dependence
        on the Skandakas-the two
        ────────────
        (55) PTS, London, 1913; also see, The Group of
             Discourses, Ⅱ(PTS, London, 1992) p.304
        (56) Leffman, Lalitavistara, p.426
        (57) `Madhyamikakarika`, 15.10

                                  422 頁

        hallmarks of the concept of `atta-can` be no means
        by associated with the `Upanisadic` `Atman-Brahman`,
        it is but natural that the `Nikaya` criticisms do
        not contain any reference to the `Upanisadic`
        concept. The post-canonical early Buddhist texts
        also never confused `atta` with the `Atman-Brahman`
        of the `Upanisads`. In the `Vajracchedika
        Prajnaparamita`(58) `atman` is used together with
        such terms as `jiva`, sattva and pudgala. All these
        terms are put in the same category and are used to
        denote different aspects of the same ego-centric
        entity. 'Sacet Bodhisattvasya sattva `samjna`
        pravarteta na sa bodhisattva iti vaktavya. tat kasya
        hetoh? na sa `Subhute` bodhisattvo vaktavyo yasya
        `atma-samjna` pravarteta, sattva-`samjna` `va`
        `jivasamjna` `va` `pudgala-samjna` `va` pravarteta'.
        'If in a Bodhisattva the perception of a being
        should take place, then he could not be called a
        Bodhisattva. And why? He is not to be called a
        Bodhisattva in whom the perception of a soul, or a
        being, or a living being, or a person would take
        place'. (59) Similary in the early `Madhyamika`
        literature we read:'Ko 'yam `atma` yo
        `'hankaravisayah'`, which may be translated as
        follows: What is this `atman` that is the domain of
        ego?(60) Here `atman` (Pali:`atta`) is
        characterised by `ahankara`. In this context we may
        refer to the definition of 'upadhi' in
        `sopadhisesanirvanam as given by `Candrakirti`(61)
        in the `Prasannapada`: tatra upadhiyate asminn
        `atmasneha ity `upadhih`,
        `upadhisabdenatmaprajnapti-nimittah
        pancopadanaskandha` ucyante'. Here the concept of
        `atma` is held to be caused by the five aggregates
        of attachment. The same idea is expressed by
        Buddhaghosa (62) while defining `'attabhava'`.
        `'Attabhava'` vuccanti `sariram`. `Khandha-pancakam`
        eva `va`, tam `upadaya pannatti-matta sabhavato`'.
        Conze translates: 'Personal existence means the
        dody, or the five Skandhas together, because
        dependent on them this mere concept comes about'.
        (63) Thus it is clear that these early Buddhist
        texts while discussing the concept of `atta` never
        thought about the `Upanisadic Atman`, but remained
        faithful to the `Nikaya`
        ────────────
        (58)`Vajracchedika Prajnaparamita`(E.Conze, Rome,
            Is. M.E.O. 1957) p.29
        (59) Also see, ibid.pp.66-67
        (60) Poussin, `Mula-Madhyamaka-Karikas`, Ch.18,p.340
        (61) Conze, ibid. p.94; Poussin, ibid. p.519-520
        (62) Visuddhimagga(h.C.Warren, 1950)Ⅸ,54
        (63) `Vajracchedika Prajnaparamita`,p.100

                                  423 頁

        characteristics of `atta`, viz. the ego-centricity
        and its invariable relationship with the skandhas.
        This point has been clearly stated by Vasubandhu. In
        his `Vimsatika-vrtti` Vasubandhu(64) states:`'Yo
        balair dharmanam` svabhavo `grahyagrahakadih`
        parikalpitas tena `parikalpitenatmana tesam
        nairatmyam`, na tv `anabhilapyenatmana yo buddhanam
        visayah` 'It is because of that imaginary `atman`
        which the ignorant people think to be the things'
        self-being consisting of subject and object etc.,
        that the things are devoid of `atman`, not because
        of the ineffable `Atman` which is the domain of the
        Buddhas'. The `atta` rejected by the Bhddhas is
        "`ahankara-visayah`" whereas the ineffable
        `Upanisadic Atman` is `'buddhanam visayah'`.
        ────────────
        (64) `Vimsatika-vrtti`(Ed. S.Levi, paris.1925)p.6

        Key words: 1.`Atta` 2.`Niratta` 3.`Anatta` 4.`Upanisad`

                                  424 頁

          初期佛教文獻的`atta、Niratta 和 Anatta

          穆克紀
          中華佛學研究所專任客座教授

          提要
              本文共分五節,討論外道持的 `atta` (我) 觀究竟如何
          ,佛教又如何用 `antta` (無我) 論來破它。
          
              第一節引《阿含》和《尼柯耶》,肯定在有為界與無為
          界都沒有 `atta` ,它只不過是想像的產品。
          
               第二節介紹近代學者對 `atta` 一詞函義的種種看法。
          其中只有 Conze 一人發現,佛教講的 `atta` 和數論所謂的
           `purusa` 有相似處。其他所有思考過此一問題的學者或許
          由於 `atta`、 `atman` 二詞對等,單單關心 `atta` 與奧義
          書 `atman` 有何等關聯,而未經系統的研究,確信二者之間
          有關係。此一觀念顯然有必要重新評估。本節則提出較客觀
          、適當的研究方法。
          
              第三節簡要敘述持 `atta` 見的常論者和持 `niratta`
          見的斷論者主要思想。
          
               第四節分析佛教如何破 `atta` 的信念。 在反駁 `atta`
          的基礎上分別擬構出常論者和斷論者所持的觀點,並發現
          佛教用三種推理方式來破 `atta` 。 尤其破常見及身見者的
          方式顯示辯論的兩種重要的特色:一、以揭發對方說法內在
          矛盾來駁斥。這個方法後來的大乘佛教用得非常成功。二、
          先接受對方部分說法,把它當做進一步顯示該說法謬誤的基
          礎。這或許可以看做大乘佛教所推崇的「方便」。
          
              第五節指出,佛陀提 `anatta` 的中道是針對常論者和
          斷論者的極端見解。同時證明常論、斷論所謂 `atta` ,並非
          奧義書的 `atman` 。