Attaa, Nirattaa, and Anattaa in the early Buddhist literature

Biswadeb Mukherjee
Chung-Hwa Buddhist Journal
Chung-Hwa Insitute of Buddhist Studies
No.6
P.391-424


. P.391 Summary The present article deals with the non-Buddhist concepts of attaa and their refutation through the doctrine of anattaa. This article is divided into five sections. Section I discusses Nikaaya passages which states which the attaa is not existent either in the sphere of the Conditioned or in the realm of the Unconditioned. It is nothing but a figment of imagination. Section II refers to the different opinions held by scholars as to the proper implications of the term attaa.Except for the lone voice of E. Conze who found similarity between the attaa and the Puru.sa of the Saa.mkhya, all other scholars who cared to ponder over this problem, seem to be preoccupied with the relationship that could exist between the attaa and the Aatman of the Upani.sads. This may be due to the fact that these two terms-attaa and Aatman-are philologically identical.The philological identity led the scholars readily to accept the view that these terms are also philosophically identical without making any further investigation into the exact onnotations of these two terms. The need for a more objective study of the problem of equation of attaa and Aatman is obvious, and a suitable methodology for such a study has been suggesed. Section III delineates the main features of the thoughts of the 'Saa'svatavaadins, Ekacasassatavaa- dins, the ucchedavaadins and the followers of the Satkaayad.r.s.ti. They were the chief propagators of the attaa heresies rejected by the Buddha. Section IV, Part A contations the criticism of all these heresies meant for the Buddhist monks. The validity of such a criticism mainly rests on the Buddha's claim to superior and higher knowledge of which the heretics know nothing.Part B of the same Section offers us the following two patterns of reasonings which P.392 were ultimately meant for the non-Buddhist ascetics and employed for the refutation of the different attaa heresies except the Ucchedavaada: I) To reject the opponent's view by showing the internal contradictions, a method which was later followed by Naagaarjuna with great success; ii) To temporarily accept a part of the opponent's view in order to show that the view as such is unacceptable. This may be taken as an instance of skillfulness of means praised so much in the Mahaayaana. Section V comes to the conclusion that the anattaa doctrine was mainly formulated keeping in view the 'saa'svatavaada and the Ucchedavaada. This is in conformity with some statements in the buddhist texts that the buddha preached the anattaa doctrine as a middle way between these two extremes. It is also clear that the attaa concepts of the 'Saa'svatavaadins and the Uccedavaadins cannot be identical with the Aatman of the Upani.sads. the Buddhist sages were aware of the fact the that the attaa rejected by the buddha is 'aha^nkaara-vi.saya.h' whereas the Upani.sadic Aatman is 'Buddhaanaam vi.saya.h'. P.393 The doctrine of anataa forms the keynote of the teachings of the Buddha and leterally means that the attaa is non-existent. The denial of the attaa finds expression in the following statement ascribed to the Buddha in the Samyutta Nikyaaya: "Sabbam bhikkhave anicca.m/sabbam bhikkhave dukkha.m/sabbam bhikkhave anattaa" (1). The chapter just preceeding the one from which we have quoted the three statements, contains such expressions as "sabbe bhikkhave jaraadhamma.m..... vyaadhidhamma.m........ mara.nadhamma.m....sa.mkilesadhama.m" etc(2). These statements leave no doubt that in all these cases we have to take the term 'sabba' as indicating the things condition. So we find that 'sabba' is a technical term and stands for the 'samsk.rta dharma'. This conclusion of ours is confirmed by the definition of 'sabba' as given in the Sabbavaggo of the Salaayatana-sa^myutta(3) : "Ki~n ca bhikkhave sabba.m/cakkhu ceva ruupaa ca/sota~nca saddaa ca/ghaana~nca gandhaa ca/jihvaa rasaa ca/kayo ca pho.t.thabba ca/mano ca dhammaa ca/idam vuccati bhikkhave sabba.m" According to this definition 'sabba' means eye and the forms, the nose and the smells, the ear and the sounds, the tongue and the tastes, the body and the tangible things, the mind and the mental objects. Here the term 'sabba' means twelve aayatana. In a more elaborate way the Buddha explains the same term while giving instructions on the giving up of the 'sabba'. He states that eye, form, eye-contact, eye-consciousness and the different feeling due to eye-contact are to be renounced. Similarly he preaches with references to other sense organs.(4) Thus the term 'sabba' fully covers the category of 'samsk.rta-dharma' and the statement "sabbam anattaa", means the conditioned is without any soul ──────────── (1) S.Vol. IV, p.28, XXXV, 43-45 (PTS,London, 1894) (2) Ibid XXXV, 34-38 (3) Ibid, p.15, XXXV, 23 (4) Katamo ca bhikkhave sabbapahaanaayo dhammo/ cakkhum bhikkhave pahaatabba.m/ruupa pahaatabbaa/cakkhuvi~n~naana.m pahaatabba.m/cak- khusamphasso pahaatabbo/yam pida.m cakkhusamphassopaccayaa uppajjati vedayita.m sukha.m vaa dukkha.m vaa adukkham asukha.m vaa/tam pi pahaatabba.m/(Sa^myutta, IV, pp15-16, XXXV, 24(PTS, London, 1894) P.394 (soul). But what about the Unconditioned? Is it also devoid of attaa? Walpolo Rahulo thinks that it is, and refers to the three statements from Dhammapada in support of his contention.(5) These statements which are very similar to the passage from the Sa^myutta Nikaaya quoted above are as follows:(i) sabbe sa^nkhaaraa dukkhaa, ii) sabbe sa^nkhaaraa aniccaa. iii), sabbe dhammaa anattaa. Rahulo thinks that while the phrase sabbe sa^nkhaaraa indicates the things conditioned, the phrase sabbe dhammaa refers to both the Conditioned and the Unconditioned. But it is difficult to accept this interpretation. We may hold that the word 'sabbe' should have the same meaning as the term 'sabbam'. viz. the conditioned things, and it is unreasonable to assume that the scope of the word 'sabba' while occuring together with the term 'dhamma' is so extended as to include even the opposite meaning, the Unconditioned. Moreover the phrase 'sabbe dhamma' has been used many times in the Buddhist scriptures to mean only the Conditioned. The Karatalaratna, a comparatively late work written by Bhaavaviveks, described 'sarvadharmaa.h' as being of dependent origin (sarvadharmaa.h.... pratiityasamut- pannaa.h......ni.hsvabhaavaa.h) (6) Again in the Culasaccakasutta of the Majjhima Nikaya (7) it is stated: "ruupa^m bhikkhave anicca^m, vedanaa aniccaa,...vi~n~naana^m anicca^m, ruupam bhikkhave anattaa, vedanaa.... sa~n~naa..... samkhaaraa...... vi~n~naanam anattaa, sabbe samkhaaraa aniccaa, sabbe dhammaa anattaa ti. "Here both the phrases 'sabbe dhammaa' and sabbe samkhaaraa obviously refer to the five skandhas. That only the conditioned things are meant here become evident when in the same sutta (8) we meet with a discussion on things which are both aniccaa and anattaa. Nibbaana is not included on this discussion. The Upasivamaanapucchaa of the Sutta nipaata (9) (1076) states that in case of nibbaana all dharmas are destroyed (sabbesu ──────────── (5) Rahulo, What the Buddha taught (Grove Press, INC.New York, 1962) , pp.57-58; Dhammapada, Chapter 20, verses 5-7. (6) Swaami Vidyaara.nya, Bauddha Dharma O Darsan, p.16 ( West Bengal State Book Boards, Calcutta, 1984) (7) Majjhima, Vol, I, p.280 (Nava Nalanda Ed.), p.228 (PTS Ed.); also see, Sa^myutta Vol. III, p.132 (8) Ibid. 282-87 (Nava Nalanda Ed.) P.395 dhammesu upahatesu) . Sabbe dhammaa has been explained as skandhas and aayatanas in the Cullaniddesa,(10) making it clear that nibbaana is outside the scope of this phrase. In the Mahaaparinibbaanasutta (11) Aniruddha explains buddha's parinibbana as 'vimokkho' of consciousness (pajjotass'eva nibbaanam vimokkho cataso). The term 'vimokkho' has been explained by Buddhaghoso in the Sumangalavilasini(12) as freedom from all dharmas (vimokkho'ti kenaci dhemmena anaabara.na). Thus the testimony of the Suttanipaata and the Mahaa parinibbaanasutta confirms that the phrase 'sabbe dhammaa' does not include nibbaana within its scope. So the things conditioned were definitely held to be devoid of attaa. But was the nirvana, the Unconditioned also bereft of attaa? Is the attaa non-existent with reference to the Unconditioned also? In the Udaana (13) nibbaana is described as anattaa which is rightly glossed as attaa-virahita in Paramatthadii pam. Thus the attaa is non-existent either as a sa.msk.rta-dharma or as an asa.msk.rta-dharma. The attaa is nothing but a figment of imagination. II ──────────── (9) PTS, London, 1913,The group of Discourses II, p.121 (PTS, London, 1992) (10)Cullaniddesa, (PTS.London, 1988) p.177, also see, The Group of Discourses II p.376 (11) Diigha, Vol II, p.157. The line "pajjotasseva nibbaana.m vimokkho cetaso" is translated in Dialogues of the Buddha, Pt. II, p.176, as "Even as a bright flame dies away, so was the last emancipation of his heart'. 'pajjota' is translated as a lamp while 'nibbaana' is taken to be blowing out of a lamp'. On the other hand M.Walche understand 'pajjota' in the sense of the 'Illumined One' and translate the same line as 'By Nibbaana the. Illumined's mind is freed' (Thus Have I Heard, London, 1987; p.271). Both these translations are not fully satisfactory PTS translates 'eva' as 'like' while it would have been better to render it as 'just, surely, indeed'. Walche omits it. As 'pajjotassa nibbaana' is compared with 'vimokkho cetaso',it would be more appropriate to translate as the 'nibbana of the Enlightened One'. So the sentence may be rendered as follows: 'The nibbaana of the Enlightened one is, indeed, the release of mind.' (12)Suma^ngala-vilaasinii, Part II, p.595 ( PTS, London, 1971) P.396 To know the reason behind the denial of attaa we have first to be clear about the exact implication of the term attaa. Scholars differ as to the precise sense in which this term has been used. But before their views were discussed it is necessary to point out that the praak.rt word attaa is the same as aatman in Sanskrit. This philological identification has led to philosophical misunderstanding among the scholars. Some scholars automatically take attaa to be the Aatman of the Upani.sads. They think that the philosophical implications of these two termsattaa and aatman-are identical and consequently the doctrine of anattaa came to mean for them the refutation of the Upani.sadic Aatman. The scholars belonging to this ──────────── (13) P.Steinthal in his edition of the Udaana (PTS, London, 1982) , p.80 adopts the following reading of the relevant verse: 'duddasam anattam naama, na hi saccam sudassanam patividdhaa tanhaa jaanato, passato n'atthi ki~ncanan ti'. In his translation F.L.Woodward reads 'anantam' (infinite) in place of anattam (Verses of Uplift, The Minor Anthologies of the Canon, Pt. II, PTS London, 1985, p.98). I prefer the reading 'anattam' due to the following considerations: Steinthal gives the variant reading 'anattam' given in the commentary (anatatan ti paa.thati) called Paramattha-dii panii which was copied in Sinhalese script for the PTS. This transcript which he calls 'C' often gives right information and corrects the incorrect readings of the other manuscripts (see, Stienthal, Udana, p.VIII).This commentary explains 'anattam' as 'attaa-virahitam'.Another manuscript which he calls 'B' as well as the Nava-Nalanda Ed. Of the Udaana follow this reading. There is no reason why the reading 'ananttam' should not be accepted. On the other hand it is difficult to agree with Woodward who accepts the reading 'anantam', as it is found only in the Nidaana.t.thakathaa of Dhammapaa- laacariya (Ed. F.L.Woodward, PTS, London, 1977, P.393) . Nidaana.t.thakathaa explains as follows: 'niccasvabhavattaa anta-virahitam amaranadhammam anirodham amatam ti attho'. 'As nibbana is permanent by nature, it is without an end, beyond death and cessation; it is immortal'. It is obvious that this definition of nibbaana also excludes attaa. Actually speaking no scriptural evidence is needed to prove that nibbaana is devoid of attaa. The concept of attaa is such that it is automatically excluded from the domain of nibbaana. P.397 group have unfaltering faith in the Buddha as the unique preacher of the True Law, and as such harbour no weakness for the honoured traditions of the Upani.sads. the view of Walpolo Sri Rahulo, an worthy representative of this group, will be presented later. On the other hand those scholars who hold both the Buddha and the Upsani.sads in high esteem do not subscribe to this view. Let us take note of the opinion of Radhakrishnan (14) who belongs to this second group of scholars. According to him the Buddha clearly tells us what the soul (attaa) is not, though he does not give us any clear account of what it is. It is, however, wrong to think that there is no soul according to the Buddha. In support of his opinion Radhakrishnan (15) refers to the dialogue between the wondering ascetic Vacchagotta which, according to him, shows that something there is, though it is not the empirical self. In another place (16) he refers to this empirical self and states that it is the false view that clamours for the perpetual continuation of this small self, which the Buddha refutes. This, (17) according to Radhakrishnan, also agrees with the statement of the Buddha that the self is neither the same nor different from the skandhas. He further states (18): " It is also clear that the reduction of the self to a number of skandhas is not ultimate. If the self is merely an impermanent compounded of body and mind....then when it disappears then there is nothing which is delivered...Freedom becomes extinction. But Nirvaa.na is timeless existence and so the Buddha admit the reality of a timeless self." Radhakrishanan appers to be of the opinion that the term 'attaa' which he translates as self has been used in two different senses. One meaning of attaa is the small self or empirical self which the Buddha rejects through the doctrine of anattaa. The other implication of the term attaa is the ture self which is same as nirvaa.na and is accepted by the Buddha. It is the identity of this true self with other things that the buddha rejects. We may now discuss the opinion of Rahulo who re- presents the other group ──────────── (14) Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, P.386 (George Allen & Unwin, London, 1977) (15) Ibid. p.386 (16) Ibid. p.388, note 1 (17) Ibid. p.387 (18) Ibid. p.451 P.398 of scholars. While explaining the doctrine of anattaa Rahulo (19) refers to the different concepts of aatman, even the concept of Brahman-Aatman of the Upani.sads and holds that the buddha was unique in rejecting all such doctrines through the doctrine of anattaa. " The idea of an abiding, immortal substance in man or outside, whether it is called Aatman, I, soul, self, or ego, is considered only a false belief, a mental projection. This is the Budhist doctrine of anttaa (20). So it appears that by the doctrine of anattaa the Buddha was denying attaa " which was accepted by every other philosophico-religious system". Rahulo seems to suggest in not so abmiguous term that even the Brahman-Aatman concept of the Upani.sads stands hereby negated. It is clear that the concept of the Upani.sadic Aatman acts as a powerful background in influencing the formulations of both the above-mentioned views. Conze, (21) on the other hand, propounds a different theory which is not connected with the Upani.sadic Aatman in any way. He is not sure what notions of an aataman were deined by the Buddha, but he believes that these notions are of two kinds, e.g.i) the ideas implied in the use of 'I' and 'mine', and ii) the philosophical opinion of the Saa^mkhya and Vaisse.sika. The basic formula absence of a self is confined to the five skandhas, and nothing is said either way about its existence quite apart from them. The Buddha never taught that the self is not, only that it cannot be apprehended. It is obvious that the solution of this knotty problem hinges on the proper understanding of the nature of attaa that was rejected by the Buddha. It is really strange that none of the scholars who suggested the equation of attaa either with the Upani.sadic Brahman-Aatman or with some other non-buddhist concepts ever tried to clearly enunciate what this attaa is. Any such suggestion without first defining the concept of attaa is bound to be methodologically unscientific and unconvincing. To arrive at a more objective conclusion the following approach may be suggested. On the one hand we should study those materials from the Nikaaya and ──────────── (19) Rahulo. What the buddha taught, p.51 (20) Ibid, p.55 (21) The Buddhist Thought in India, pp.38-39 (George Allen & Unwin, London, 1962) P.399 Aagama which are more or less descriptive in nature, Such materials provide us with legends and other informantions about the attaa philosophy dominant in the region where the Buddha was preaching his anattaa doctrine, and so engaged his attention. The reason for doing so is the justifiable surmise that the attaa concept or concepts, the negation of which forms the core of buddhism, should find some mention in this descriptive type of scripture. On the other hand we should carefully scrutinise another type of material contained in the Buddhist scripture which is more critical and philosophical in nature, and acquaints us with detailed argumengs justifying the rejection of the attaa philosophy. Out of such study will also emerge the atta concept or concepts which the Buddha was rejecting. The study of these two types of materials will enable us to form a complete idea of the different attaa concepts the Buddha discarded as false views. It is only then we would be in a position to reliably know whether the Upani.sadic concept of Aatman-Brahman was rejected or not. The major non-buddhist concepts of attaa criticised in the Nikaayas and Aagamas many be broadly divided nito four main categories dealing with a) Satkaayad.r.s.ti, b), 'Sa'svatavaada, c) Ekaccassatavaada, and d) ucchedavaada. We will discuss these heresies in the order given here. III a) Satkaayad.r.s.ti : In the Sa^myutta Nikaaya (22) we come across the following description of a false view which later came to be known as Satkaayad.r.s.ti: " Those recluses and Brahmanas who while seeing in various ways see the attaa (soul), they actually see the five aggregates of attachment or any of them. Which five? In this connection, monks, an uneducated ordinary person... envisages matter as a soul, or a soul possessing matter, or matter in a soul, or a soul in matter. Or he envisages, feeling, perception, the gormative forces, or consciousness as a soul, possessed by a soul, in a soul, or soul in them. Envisaging thus he gets a thought "I am"...Being ignorant he thinks this, or "I am this" or "I shall be" "I shall not be" or I shall be material "or" I shall be having perception "or" I shall be ──────────── (22) Sa^myutta, Vol.III 46f; Taisho, vol.II, p.11b1ff. A.K. Warder,Indian Buddhism, pp.123ff P.400 without perception (a-samj~nin)" or "I shall have neither perception nor non-perception. But one who is educated, abandons ignorance and gets knowledge... and does not have any of these thoughts." The passage quoted above shows that the attaa in which these recluses and Braahma.nas believed could be in four different ways connected with the five skandhas and this connection is constant. The existence of an attaa without any reference to the skandhas was unthinkable. This association of the soul with the skandhas gave rise to certain ego-centric thoughts in which both these elements-the soul and the skandhas-are present, e.g. "I am this" "I shall be material" etc. Here we have a succinct description of a false view that draws our attention to its two main features: 1) attaa refers to an individual soul whose essence consists of an awareness of 'I' (22a); 2) attaa is invariably connected with the skandhas. Its existence is always conceived in association with skandhas. This heresy, as already noted, came to be known as satkaayad.r.s.ti (Pali: Sakkaayadi.t.thi). The term satkaaya refers to the five aggregates of attachment (pa~ncupaadaanakkhand- haa) (23) and Satkaayad.r.s.ti to a false view that fails to see the skandhas merely as skandhas, but always views them through the prism of an attaa. The most subtle from of satkaayad.r.s.ti is discernible in the feeling " I am" which lingers in anybody who is spiritually below the status of an arhat. He may no longer consciously believe in ──────────── (22a) In the Alagaddupamasuttam of the Majjhima Nikaaya (PTS), Vol. I, pp.138ff. (Nalanda Ed.), Vol.I, pp.185 ff. We read that the feelings of 'I' and 'mine' are interdependent. And with "I" and "mind" to be really and truly existing, the possibility of this false view would also be there: "That is the world, that is attaa. I shall be after death, everlasting, abiding eternal, unchanging and I shall remain as such for eternity". The feeling of 'I'and 'mine' being absent, the possibility of the false view would not be there. So a staunch belief in the reality of 'I' and 'mine' is the fulcrum on which the illusory image of an eternal soul rests. (23) Satkaaya or Sakkaaya means pa~ncupaadaanakkhandhaa or five aggregates of attachment: "Pa~nca kho ime.... upaadaanakkhandhaa sakkaayo vutto bhagavataa seyyathidam rupupaadaanakkhandho, vedanupaadaanakkhandho. Sa~n~nupaadaanakkhandho, vi~n~naanupaadaanakkhandho, samkhaarupaadaana- kkhandho (Cullavedallasutta, Majjhima Nikaaya, Vol.I, pp.369-70(nalanda Ed.), p.299 (PTS). P.401 it, he may even intellectually refute it, but he is not yet free from the vestige of this pernicious heresy.(24) We may refer to passage in the ko'sa literature that helps us to understand more clearly the different modes of relationship existing between the soul and the five skandhas (Conze, p.33). This passage, like the Sa^myutta Nikaaya account, distinguishes between the twenty bases of grasping at the notion of soul. One regards (1-5) the soul as the five skandhas, as the flame of a lamp is identical with its visual appearance; (6-10) the soul as having or possessing the five skandhas, like the shadow of a thing; (11-15) the skandhas in the soul, as the scent in a flower; (16-20) the soul in the skandhas, as the gem in the casket.(25) ──────────── (24) In this connection we may refer to the episode of khemaka recorded in the Sa^myutta Nikaaya, Vol. III, pp.127ff. (PTS Ed.) Some monks ask Khemaka whether he sees in the five aggreates of attachment any self (attaa) or anything pertaining to self (attaniiya). Khemaka replies in the negative but at the same time admits that he is not yet an arhat. "I am not an arhat free from all impurities, Oh friends, with regard to the five aggregates of attachment. I have a feeling 'I am' but I do not clearly see 'This is I am'". Then Khemaka explains what he calls 'I am' is neither matter, feeling, perception, mental formation (sa^nkhaara) nor consciousness nor anything without them. But he has the feeling 'I am' with regard to the five skadhas, though he could not see clearly 'This is I am'. He says it is like the smell of a flower, it is neither the smell of the petals, nor of the colours, nor of the pollens, but the smell of the flower. Khemaka further explains that this feeling 'I am' disappears when one progresses further, just as the chemical smell of a freshly washed cloth disappears when it is kept in a box. (25) See, E.Conze, Buddhist Thought in India, p.33. It is to be noted that the same comparison of attaa with smell of a flower also occurs in the Sa^myutta Nikaaya (see, note no.24). We should, however, observe that though Khemaka feels 'I am' he does not treasure this feeling; he wants to get rid of it as something unreal. But to a follower of 'Saa'svatavaada this feeling indicates something real which is the very essence of his eternal being. The spiritual experience is same in both the cases, though the wisdom needed to interpret the experience correctly is absent in case of the 'Saa'svatavaadins. P.402 This account of the Sathaayad.r.s.ti acquaints us with the most basic form of attaa heresy. Satkaayad.r.s.ti merely postulates a relationship between the soul and the five skandhas. It neither advocates the eternity of the soul nor holds the soul to be co-terminous with the body. Satkaayad.r.s.ti is neither 'Saa'svatavaada nor Ucchedavaada. But the following statement recorded in the Sa^myutta Nikaaya (26) imaa kho gahapati ditthiyo sakkaayaditthiya sati honti-shows that the satkaaya d.r.s.ti is the root cause of all other heresies, including the 'Saa'svatavaada and the Ucchedavaada. A person believing in a soul and having desire for existence (bhava-t.r.s.naa) willingly believes that the soul survies the body and accepts the false view of its permanetnt existence (bhava-d.r.s.ti). On the other hand, a person thirsting for non-existence (vibhava-t.r.s.naa), willingly believes that death is the ultimate end of every thing, and comes to believe in the false view of non-existence (Vibhavad.r.s.ti) the annihilation of soul after death (Ucchedavaada).(27) b) 'Saa'svatavaada: The account of the 'Saa'svatvaada as given in the Brahma-jaalasutta (28) may be abridged as follows:- There are recluses and Brahmanas who accept the philosophy of eternalism (sassatavaada) and proclaim that both the soul and the world are eternal. And why they do so? Some recluse and Brahmana by means of exertion and proper mental attention attains to such a cencentration of mind that they are able to recall to mind many hundreds of thousands of past births. And they think: "There ──────────── (26) Sa^myutta, Vol.IV, p.287 (27) Lamotte, Indian Buddhism, pp.35,48,51. In this connection we may refer to the Sattaasavasutta, Majjhima Nikaaya, (Nalanda Ed. Vol.I, pp.12-13), which also states that it is due to ego-centric thoughts (e.g. atthi me atta etc.) that such a wrong view arises: "This is my self, which speaks and feels, which experiences the fruits of good and bad actions now here, now there, this self is permanent, stable, everlasting, unchanging, remaining the same for ever and ever." This false view is given the designation of 'Saa'svatavaada in the Sa^myutta Nikaaya; "That is the self, that is the world (loka) . He takes rebirth, he is eternal, stable, unchanging - this is the eternalist veiw-point." Cf. S. Part III, pp.98-99; 182 (28) Diigha Nikaaya, Vol. I ( PTS Ed. By T.W.Rhys Davids) London, 1973, pp.13-14; T.W.Rhys Davids, Dialogues of the Buddha, Part I, pp.27-28(PTS, London, 1977) P.403 I was born of such a name (eva.m-naamo), of such a lineage and caste (eva.m-gotto, eva.m-va.n.no).(29) My food was such (eva.m-aahaaro) . I was the experiencer of such pleasures and pains (evam-sukha-dukkha-pa.tisa.mvedii) and had such a span of life (evam-aayu-pariyanto). Falling from there I was born here." (30) Thus they remember their past existences in full detail. And each of them says to himself:"sassato attaa ca loko ca va~njho kuta.t.tho esika.t.thaayi.thito, te ca sattaa sandhaavanti sa.msaranti cavanti upapajjanti, atthi tveva sassata-saman ti." (31) T.W.Rhys Davids translates as follows: "The soul is eternal; and the world giving birth to nothing new, is steadfast as a moutain-peak, as a pillar firmly fixed; and that though these living creatures transmigrate and pass away, fall from one state of existence and spring up in another, yet they are (atthi) for ever and ever." (32) Though this translation tallies with the traditional Buddhist explanation, it is difficult to accept it, as it raises some problems. From the legend we have seen that the living beings in this world could only remembers the details of their past lives here. And an awareness of an unchangeable 'I' (cf. I was born with such a name etc.) links all these past lives together and gives rise to the notion of an eternal soul (attaa). The same soul was thought to be born again and again as different individuals. The attaa and sattaa are not identical. The skandhas are admitted to be different in each of these births, though the attaa characterised by the awareness of an'I' remains unchanged. The above translation from Rhys Davids of the stock description of 'Saa'svatavaada is not in aggreement with the implications of the 'Saa'svatavaada legend. In this translation not only the two verbs of motion ( sandhaavanti and sa.msaranti) indicating repeated deaths and rebirths and so underlining changes are connected with the sattaa but also the verb of existence (atthi) indicating permanency becomes associated with the same sattaa. If we accept this translation we have to admit that the 'Saa'svatavaadins thought the concept of eternity to be compatible with the ──────────── (29) In the Mahaapadaanasutta we have evam-jaati in place of evam-vanno. Both the terms mean social class or caste. (Diigha Nilaaya, Vol. II.p.8) (30) Diigha Nikaaya, Vol.I,p.13 (PTS,London, 1975) (31) Ibid, p.15 (32) Dialogues of the buddha, Part I.p.28(PTS, London, 1977) P.404 notion of change. The soul's enternity was not at variance with its identity with the changeable skandhas. But there is no reason to believe that the 'Saasvatavaadins were so unrealistic as to support such an unreasonable view. We have seen that according to the 'Saa'svatavaada the eternal soul characterised by a sense of 'I' was different from the changing individuals. Moreover, other religious groups contemporary of the 'Saa'svatavaadins were also not supporters of such a view. The ucchedavaadins (33) took the soul to be identical with the skandhas, and consistent with this view they held that the soul is destroyed together with the body. The Ekaccasassatavaadins (34) believed the Mahaabrahmaa to be eternal as they did not appear to have known that the Mahaabrahmaa was also identical with the skandhas, created, and subject to death. All the religious groups including the 'Saa'svatavaadins thus seem to have held the view that the soul to be eternal must have an existence independent of the skandhas. So the translation making the sattaa eternal cannot be accepted. The only other possibility is to take 'atthi' in the sense of a singular number and to connect it with 'attaa'. Then we get the following translation: "The soul is eternal; and the world giving birth to nothing new, is steadfast as a mountain-peak, as pillar firmly fixed; and these living beings move on and on, transmigrate, fall from one state of existence, rise up in another, but (the soul) exists for eternity." For our purpose it is, however, important to know how the buddhists would understand this philosophy. From our discussion of the Satkaayad.r.s.ti it is clear that according to the Buddhist's interpretation of the false view the soul must be either identical with or closely related to the Skandhas. This relation is such that the existence of a soul apart from the skandhas is unthinkable. The changes which the skandhas undergo even during one's lifetime are obvious. Moreover the acceptance of the repeated deaths and rebirths shows that the skandhas do not remain unchanged. In short, according to the buddhist interpretation, the 'Saa'svatavaadins admitted the changeable nature of the skandhas, accepted the close relationship existing between the soul and the skandhas, and yet held the soul to be eternal (sassato). This also seems to be the opinion of Buddhaghosa (35) as ──────────── (33) Diigha Nikaya, Vol I, see, p.34; also see, p.12 (34) See, p.10 ff. P.405 expressed in the Suma^ngalavilaasinii, But, as already shown, Buddhist presentation of the eternalism is not the same as the original philosiophy of the 'Saa'svatavaadins. The 'Saa'svatavaadins themselves regarded 'attaa' to be independent of body and mind, i.e. of the skandhas, to use the Buddhist terminology. This seems to be reason why the 'Saa'svatavaadins themselves did not relate the soul to any of the skandhas in the stock description of their own philosophy. Even the logicians and thinkers (takkii, viima^nsii) (36) among them have nothing to say about the relationship existing between the soul and the skandhas. Whatever may be the case, it is of no consequence for our present study that the Buddhist presentation of the attaa of the 'Saa'svatavaadins does not tally with the original concept. What really matters is the idea the Buddhists had of such a concept. For when they reject a concept of an eternal soul, they do so in the light of their own understanding of it. So it is important to take note of their idea of the attaa concept which may be described as follows: The attaa is an eternally existent indiv idual soul which is either identical with the skandhas or so closely attains liberation nor gets annihilated. C) Ekaccasassatavaada: A concept of attaa different from that of the eternalists has been recorded in the Brahmajaalasutta of the Diigha-Nikaaya.(37) This is the concept of an eternal soul unique to the Mahaabrahmaa as held by the followers of the Ekaccasassatavaada. The Buddha in order to explain the origin of the Ekaccasassatavaada relates the following legend about the past lives of the upholders of this philosophy: When the world system dissolves the beings are reborn in the Aabhassara world. They are made of mind. Now the world system begins to come into exitence and an empty Braham-vimaana (Brahma-palace) appears. One of the beings at the end of merits or span of life falls from the Aabhassara world and is reborn in the Brahma-palace. There he lives, made of mind (manomayo), feeding on joy (piiti-bhakkho), radiating light. Etc. and thus does remain there for a ──────────── (35) Suma^ngalavilaasinii, Vol.I, p.105(PTS, London, 1968) (36) Diigha Nikaaya, Vol.I,p.16 (37) Ibid.pp.17-19; Dialogues of the Buddha, Part I, pp.30-32 P.406 long time. And the feels lonely and longs for companions. Just then some beings die in the Aabhassara world and are born in the Brahma-palace. They are just like the being who was first born. As these beings were born after he desired for company, he thought himself to be Brahmaa Mahaabrahmaa, Creator, Father of all that are and are to be. And the other beings also thought that they have been created by Mahaabrahmaa. Their lives are of shorter duration than that of Mahaabrahmaa. They die in the Brahma-palace and are reborn here in this world. Here one of them leads a religious life and can remember his past existence in the Brahma-palace, but not beyond that. He thinks of Mahaabrahmaa as creator permanent, fixed, eternal, of a nature which is not subject to transformation (nicco, dhuvo, sassato, aviparinaamadhammo) while he regards himself and other beings as created by Mahaabrahmaa, impermanent, not fixed, eternal, and having the nature of dying (ancicaa, addhuvaa, appayukaa, cavanadhammaa). The last part of the above account seems to be a stock description which formed a part of the original philosophy of the Ekaccasassatavaadins. According to their philosophy only the uncreated is eternal while the created is impermanent. Only Mahaabrahmaa is eternal and the other beings are impermanent. The information that Mahaabrahmaa was made of mind were most probably not included in their philosophy, for it is not mentioned in the utterance of him who remembers his past existence. Otherwise we have to assume that according to the Ekaccasassatavaadins mind can be both created and uncreated. So it appears that this extra bit of information has been added in accordance with the Buddhist dogma. Thus as per the understandings of the Buddhists, the followers of the Ekaccasassatvaada believed in an eternal soul only in case of mahaabrahmaa and this soul was made of mind, uncreated and immortal. Two other groups of the Ekaccasassatavaadins (38) believed in many eternal individual souls. But the eternity is not absolute in these cases; it may be lost either due to the lack of self-controll or due to envy. The fourthe group of the Ekaccasassatavaadins (39) were comprised of the logicians and the thinkers who concluded by reasoning that there are two souls, one impermanent and the other ──────────── (38) Diigha Nikaaya, Vol.I, pp.19-21 (39) Ibid, p.21 P.407 permanent. The soul consisting of ear, nose tongue and body is impermanent, not fixed, not eternal and having the changeable nature. But the soul which is thought or mind or consciousness (cittan ti va mano ti va vi~n~naanan ti va) is permanent, eternal etc. d) Ucchedavaada: the seven groups of Ucchedavaadins (40) identified an individual soul variously with physical body, or sensual desire, or mind, or infinite space, or infinite consciousness, or nothingness, or neither perception nor not perception. The first group believed in one soul made of gross matter while the other groups believed in more than one souls. And all these groups upheld the doctrine that the soul is annihilated with the destruction of the body. It appears that even before the Buddhists the Ucchedavaadins denied the belief in an eternal individual soul (attaa) which was identical with one of the skandhas. Therefore this philosophy came to be known as the doctrine of nirattaa. So far we have discussed the Satkaayad.r.s.ti, 'Saa'svatavaada, Ekaccasasvatavaada and the Ucchedavaada, and these are the only dominant heresies regarding attaa and relevant to our study that have been recorded in the Aagamas and Nikaayas. (41) Presumably these were the four main type of heresies that attracted the attention of the Buddha and the early Buddhists. It is obvious that the attaa concepts discussed in the Ucchedavaada and Satkaayad.r.s.ti can in no way be connected with the problem of attaa's identity with the Upani.sadic Aatman. It is only ths 'Saa'svatavaada and Ekaccasassatavaada concept that deserves to be considered in tis connection. In course of our discussion we have noted the following characteristics of an eternal soul as envisaged by the followers of the 'Saa'svatavaada and Ekaccasassatavaada. The first group of Ekaccasassatavaada believed that only the ──────────── (40) Ibid, pp.34-35 (41) I have not mentioned the other attaa heresies described in the Brahmajaalasutta, as they are not radically different from what we have discussed in the present article. All these heresies are also based on the Satkaayad.r.s.ti and so share the characteristics of the Satkaayad.r.s.ti. These heresies must also be partially similar to the 'Saa'svatavaadins or the Ekaccasassatavaadins. I could not trace any other sutta devoted to the rejection of any of these heresies. The Buddhists themselves, it seems, did not think it necessary to discuss these false views separately and elaborately. P.408 soul of Mahaabrahmaa, who is uncreated, is eternal. But the 'Saa'svatavaada and the other groups of Ekaccasassatavaada recognise numerous, eternal, individual souls who are either identical with the skandhas or so closely related to them as to be dependent on them for their very existence. The second and third groups of the Ekaccasassatavaadins, however, are of the opinion that the eternity is not absolute, for the beings die if they indulge in sensual pleasures or are afflicted with jealousy. The first type of Ekaccasassatavaada explicitly states that the souls, including that of the Mahaabrahmaa, are made of mind. This view seems to have been accepted by the second and third groups of the Ekaccasassatavaadins who made the eternity of the individual souls dependent on the purity of mind. According to the fourth group of the Ekaccasassatavaadins which consists of the logicians and the thinkers, the individual soul is identical with citta or manas or vij~naana. Thus we find that the Ekaccasassatavaada concept of soul belonged to the sphere of mind and at least in most cases could not rise beyond the Ruupaloka. Moreover the eternal souls are confined within space and time and are characterised by the subject-object split. The Upani.sadic Aatman, on the other hand, is not an individual soul. The Aatman is the supreme reality, the only Being that is beyond speech, beyond the reach of mind and the notion of space. And such an Aatman can by no strech of imagination be equated with any of the skandhas. In short, the sassato attaa of the Buddhist scriptures and the Aatman of the Upanisads are two diametrically opposing points of view. So long we have discussed scriptural materials which are more or less descriptive in nature. Now we pay attention to a more critical type of Aagama-Nikaaya passages which acquaint us with the reasons for the rejection of different types of ataa heresies, and thereby provide us with some extra details regarding these heresies. IV We have seen that four kinds of relationship between the attaa and the skandhas were recognised. Out of these only one type of relationship viz. that of identity between the attaa and the skandhas, finds prominent mention in the Nikaayas and the Aagamas. This appears to have been the dominant heresy at the P.409 time of the Buddha. Only in a few cases the early buddhist canon takes note of other types of relationship, viz. attaa has skandhaka or attaa is not a particular type of skandhaka. Again the nature and contents of such a criticism of attaa heresy vary depending on the type of persons for whom it was meant. The discourses which are held for the benefit of the Buddhist monks are quite different from those meant for non-Buddhist asceties. With these preliminary remarks we will proceed to arrange the relevant materials according to the type of heresies criticised and the type of persons addressed. A: Criticism of heresies meant for the Buddhist monks i) Rejection of Satkaayad.r.s.ti: The sa^myutta passage referred to above is a plain form of instruction discarding the heresy of Satkaayad.r.s.ti. the Buddha points out that some recluses and Brahmans by erroneous observations of the skandhas give rise to the false notion of a soul, but those who are wise never make this mistake. Here the talk is about the mere existence of a soul with reference to the skandhas, and not the eternity or impermanence of soul. It is apparent that the Buddha is rejecting the Satkaayad.r.s.ti. The Buddha does not find it necessary to offer any extra argument in favour of his view, as he addresses his own disciples who have absolute faith in his wisdom. ii) Criticism of 'Saa'svatavaada: In the account of the Brahmajaalasutta which we have already discussed, the Buddha gives critical description of the heresy of 'Saa'svatavaada in the form of a legend. He points out that some recluses and Brahmanas believe in eternal individual soul for they can remember their past lives in this world. The sutta implies that the memory of the past lives is genuine though the interpretation of such experiences is wrong. In this passage no logical argument is advanced justifying the rejection of this heresy. It will, however, be clear later from our discussion of another passage from the same sutta that the Buddha rejects this view on the basis of his more extensive knowledge and higher knowledge. iii) Criticism of Ekaccasassatavaada: Like the legend about the 'Saa'svatavaada, the legend concerning the Ekaccasassatavaada in the Brahmajaalasutta implicitly contains the criticism of the concept of an eternal soul. The legend states that P.410 the beings who died in the Brahmaa world were born in this world. While in this world they could remember their past birth in the Brahma-vimaana, but had no knowledge of their still earlier birth in the Aabhassara world, nor could they know that Mahaabrahmaa is also subject to death. This legend suggests that the incomplete experience coupled with imperfect knowledge led these beings to interpret wrongly their genuine spiritual experiences. Consequently they came to believe in the false notion of an eternal Mahaabrahmaa who is made of mind. So the Buddha is here criticising Ekaccasassatavaada on the basis of his more extensive knowledge. iv) Criticism of heresies in general: There is no legend criticising the Ucchedavaada. This is because the Ucchedavaada tradition most probably did not record any legend justifying this philosophy. The Ucchedavaada philosophy only recognised the present life and denied the existence of any life before birth and after death. So there was no scope for the development of any such legend. In the Brahmahaakasyttam however, we come across a general criticism of all the false views noted in this sutta.(42) Here the criticism is based on the more extensive knowledge and higher knowledge of the Buddha. The passage in question states that the Buddha knows of all these false views and also knows of into what sort of future existences fall those who grasp at and become attached to such views. Knowing this and knowing (other) higher things (ta~n ca Tathaagato pajaanaati, tato ca uttariitaram pajaanaati ) the Tathaagata does not get involved, he knows about extinction; and having truly known the rising and passing away of sensations (vedanaanam samudaya~n ca atthamagama~n ca), their taste, danger, their not being the refuge, Tathaagata, due to the non-attachment, is free (vimutto). These are those other things, profound, difficult, to understand.. not to be grasped at by mere logic, which Tathaagata having himself realised and seen face to face, has set forth." The higher knowledge which is profound and beyond logic is different from the knowledge of future existences and past lives of the beings. The phrase-"knowing this and knowing(other) higher things"-clearly shows that two different types of knowledge are referred to. The higher knowledge refers to the ──────────── (42) Diigha Nikaaya, Vol.I, pp.16-17, 21-22, 24, 28, 29 etc. P.411 rising and passing away of vadanaa (sensation or feeling),i.e.the knowledge of the pa.ticcasamuppaada which only the Buddha possessed. That the statement reggarding 'vedanaa' refers to the truth of the dependent origination is confirmed by another passage of the same sutta (D. 1.3.71). all the false views are rejected because they are contradicated by the law of dependent origination. Of all the links of the Pa.ticcasamuppaada, Vedanaa is specially mentioned, for the awareness of 'I' is directily dependent on vedanaa. In corroboration of the the conclusion reached above we may take note of another sutta where the rejection of a false view on the basis of pa.ticca- samuppaada is explicitly mentioned. V) Rejection of the Ekaccasassatavaada:The Buddha in his instruction to his disciple Keva.t.taputto Saati is rejecting the Ekaccasassatvaaada on the basis of pa.ticcasamuppaada.(43) Saati gave out that it is the self-same vij~naana that passes from one existence to another. Here Saati is speaking in favour of 'Saa'svatavaada. This statement is elaborated in the Papa~ncasudani (44) to bring out its full significance: 'That which speaks, experiences now here now there, the fruits of his good and evil actions is that consciousness (vij~naana) that I am speaking about.' The same vij~naana is enjoying the fruits of his actions. This is the same as preaching 'Saa'svatavaada as it will be clear from a passage of the Sabbaasavasutta of the Majjhima Nikaaya and a passage from the Sa^myutta Nikaaya. The Majjhima passage runs thus (45): Atha va pana assa evam di.t.thi hoti: yo me ayam attaa vado vedeyya tatra tatra kalyanapapakanam vipaakam patisa.mvedeti so kho pana me ayam attaa nicco dhuvo sassato aviparinamodhammo sassatisamam tath'eva thassati' 'Or a wrong view occurs to him thus: the soul of mine that speaks, experiences now here and now there the fruits of his good and evil actions is indeed that soul of mine that is permanent, stable, not subject to change, that will stand firm for eternity.' The Sa^myutta passage (46) states: One and the same person both acts and ──────────── (43) M.I, Mahaata~nhaasa^nkhayasutta, pp.256ff. idam vi~n~naana^m sandhaavanti, sa.msaranti ana~n~nam. Ibid. p.256 (44) Papa~ncasuudanii, Vol.II, p.305 (PTS, London, 1979) (45) Majjhims, Vol.I,p.8(PTS, London, 1976) (46) Sa^myutta Nikaaya, Vol.II, p.20 P.412 experiences (the results). This Kassapa which you called at first'suffering self-wrought' ammounts to the Eternalist theory.(47) It is also to be noted that Saati is identifying the eternal soul with the vij~naana only. This reminds us of the view of the logicians among the Ekaccasassatavaadins who held that indriya etc. are impermanent while the citta (thought), or manas (mind), or vij~naana (consciousness) is eternal. So the eternalism which Saati is preaching actually ammounts to the Ekaccasassatavaada of the logicians. To reject this view the Buddha refers to the law of dependent origination (pa.ticcasamuppaada). The Bud- dha condemned the view of Saati and corrected him by pointing out that vij~naana can only originate through cause and conditions (a~n~natra paccayaa na'tthi vi~n~naanassa sambhavo ti) (48) and so cannot be eternal. In the preceding pages we have dealt with such criticisms of the false views regarding attaa as were meant for the loyal disciples of the Buddha. For his disciples the unquestionable veracity of these criticisms ultimately rests on their unflagging faith in the claim of the Buddha to the more extensive and higher types of knowledge. It was not necessary for the Buddha to analyse critically the different heresies in order to expose the flaws in them, or to adduce extra reasons to justify their rejection. The approach, however, changes when the discourses are meant for the non-Buddhist ascetics. B : Criticism of heresies meant for non-Buddhist as- cetics i) Rejection of Ssaa'svatavaada: (49) The Anattaa-lakkhana-sutta of the Sa6myutta Nikaaya (III XXII, 59) (50) while giving a clear exposition of the anattaa doctrine, ──────────── (47) Kindred Sayings, Vol.II, p.16 (PTS, London, 1982) (48) Majjhima, Vol.I, p.259. It appears that Saati misunderstood the Buddhist doctrine of rebirth. It is said in the Sa^myutta Nikaaya (I, 122; II, 67, 103) that it is only when vi~n~naana obtains a footing on something (aarammana) that there is the possiblity of the birth of a being, and not otherwise, and the moment the vi~n~naana ceases (cuti), one is regarded as dead. Also see, Nalinaksha dutt, Early Monastic Buddhism, Vol.I,P.255 (Calcutta, 1941). (49) Sa^myutta, Vol.II, pp.66-68 (PTS.London, 1960); Vinaya, Vol.I, p.13-14 (PTS,London, 1964) P.413 adduces reasons for the denial of attaa in the following manner: From (ruupa) is not soul (attaa). If it were, this form could not turn oppressive, and with regard to form it would be possible to achieve the intention that "let my body be thus, let my body be not thus". And so with vedanaa, sa~n~naa, sa^mkhaara, and vi~n~naana. "What do you think is form permanent or impermenet?" "It is impermanent, Oh Lord". "But is the impermanent ill (dukkha) or ease (sukha)?" "It is ill, Oh Lord". "But is it fitting to consider that which is impermanent linked to suffering, doomed to reversal as 'this is mine, I am this, this is my soul"'. "No, indeed, Oh Lord". And so for vedanaa, sa~n~naa ect. Therefore whatever form there is, past or future, inner or outer, gorss or subtle, low or exalted, near or far away, would be seen by right wisdom as it really is, i.e. "all this form is not really mine, I am not really this, this is not my soul (attaa)." And so vedanaa, sa~n~naa etc. Seeing this the well-disciplined holy disciple become disgusted with the skandhas." From a careful study of the passage quoted above the concept of the attaa rejected here clearly emerges. The ruupa and other skandhas cannot be attaa for they turn oppressive and cannnot be changed according to one's liking. So it follows that the attaa or the individual soul enjoys complete self-mastery and remains ever happy. Moreover the five skandhas are not attaa for they are impermanent and subject to change and suffering. This shows that the attaa concept rejected here was believed to be identical with the skandhas, permanent, changeless, happy and characterised by an awareness of an 'I' and 'mine'. So the concept of attaa which emerges wholly conforms to the Ssaa'svatavaada. Two opposing trends of thought are discernible in this sutta. One represent the viewpoint of the 'Saa'svatavaada as presented above. The other trend shows the Buddha's acceptance of the notion of I and mine as a basis for further argumentation in order to disprove the soul's identity with the skandhas. The line of reasoning, partly explicit and partly implicit, may be presented thus: the idea of 'I' and 'mine' is the characteristic feature of attaa and implies complete self-mastery of oneself. Wha t one refers to as 'I' and 'mine' must be its own master. Moreover the individual soul is permanent. But the body (ruupa) is beyond one's control. ──────────── (50) Diigha Nikaaya, Vol.I, pp.179, 182 ff, ; Dialogues of the Buddha, Part I, p.246ff. Also see, A.K.Warder, Indian Buddhism (Motilal Banarasidas, Delhi, 1991) pp.124ff. P.414 It grows, becomes old and ultimately dies without anybody being able to do anything to arrest this process. In short this philosophy upholds the self-mastery and permanency of an individual soul but advocates in the same breath the identity of the soul with the five skandhas which are impermanent and lack self-mastery. Thus it is clear that the viewpoint of the 'Saa'svatavaadins suffers from internal contradiction and cannot be accepted. It should be noted that the Buddha did not criticise this philosophy on the basis of any Buddhist doctrine. The impermanence of body etc, is a matter of common experience and no higher philophy is needed to prove it.The Buddha neither referred to the skandhas constituting a being nor to the law of pa.ticcasamuppaada in order to deny the existence of a permanent ego-centric entity. Rather he made use of the notion of 'I' which is taken to be the tell-tale sign of an individual soul to refute the 'S aa'svatavaada. This approach appears to be all the more intriguing as the Buddha is preaching to his own disciples, and not to the non-Buddhist ascetics. And from the dialogue between the Buddha and his disciples it is obvious that his disciples has not turned into supporters of this false view, but had remained faithful to his teachings. Moreover it would be preposterous to hold that the Buddha actually supported the existence of a permanent individual soul, although he denied its identity with the five skandhas. What, then, is the reason for this particular mode of preaching? We can reasonably surmise that he was instructing his disciples how to meet the challenges of such an erroneous view. The inadvisability of trying to discard this false view by referring to the Buddhist doctrine is obvious, for the non-Buddhists cannot be expected to have any faith in the teachings of the Buddha. So the Buddha was teaching his disciples how such false doctrines could be successfully countered even while basing one's argumants on such articles of faith as forming an integral part of the philosophy they were criticising. He was trying to show how the logical implications of one aspect of this false doctrine would render null and void another aspect of the same doctrine. In other words the Buddha was teaching his disciples to expose the contradictions inherent in the doctrines of the 'Saa'svatavaadins in such a way that even the upholdres of this philosophy would be forced to admit the justification of the criticism. In the Anattaa-lakkhana-sutta the point which the Buddha drives home is that the logical implications of the notion of 'I' P.415 which were acceptable to the protagonists of this philosophy, would contradict the other part of the philosophy, viz. the identity of the individual soul with the skandhas. It is also clear that the sutta was ultimately meant for the 'Saa'svatavaadins themselves. ii) a)The Po.t.thapadasutta and the rejection of Satkaayad.r.s.ti: this sutta starts with a discussion of the rising and the cessation of perception (sa~n~naa or abhisa~n~na) and then follows it up with a judgement about the problem of identity between the soul and perception. We will just have a glimpse of the discussion as it will help us to understand the nature of perception. The Buddha gave a gradual discoures on the higher and higher stages of perception leading to the summit of perception ( sa~n~naggam) and then to the cessation of perception (nirodha). Except the final stage, at every other stage a perception of a lower type is replaced by a perception of a higher type. The Buddha showed that a certain type of perception arose due to a cetain type of thinking, a cetain type of mental training. When the thinking ceased, the perception also ceased. With the cessation of all thoughts, the possibility of the rising of any new perception comes to an end. Next Po.t.thapaada raises the question of a soul. "Is perception the soul of a man, Sir, or is perception one thing and soul another?" The Buddha asked, "What, now, Po.t.thapaads, do you assume a soul?" "I presume a gross soul sir, material, made of four great elements, feeding on solid food". "Yet if your soul were gorss, Po.t.thapaada, material, made of four gross elements feeding on solid food, in that case for you perception would be one thing, soul another. Just let this gross soul be, Po.t.th- apaada, for then a man's perception occurs as one thing, ceases as another thing". Po.t.thapaada next proposes to assume a mental soul, with perfect faculties, complete in its faculties. The Buddha's objection remains the same: perception would then occur as one thing but cease as another thing. Lastly Po.t.tapaada proposes an immaterial soul, consisting of perception. The objection of the Buddha is still the same. The denial of the identity between the soul and perception is based on the following pattern of reasoning. If the soul is material like body, then the soul cannot be identical with perception. For in that case the perception would be rising as one thing and ceasing as another. It means that as long as the perception is in existence, it can be assumed to be soul (as body). But when it ceases to be, it P.416 can no longer be equated with the soul, for the living material soul would be still in existence. Hence the statement about the perception as rising as one and ceasing as another. This reasoning also holds good while showing the difference between the perception and soul as mind, for the cessation of a particular perception does not mean the annihilation of mind. But this type of reasoning is not valid when one assumes the soul to be made of perception. In this case the cessation of perception will auto- matically mean the annihilation of soul, and con- sequently the argumant that the perception ceases as another is no longer tenable. This part of the discussion appears to be a later mechanical addition. Whatever may be the case, it is obvious that Po.t.thapaada is equating attaa with a skandhaka. In his query about the identity of the soul with perception as well as in his suggestion that the soul may be made of four gross elements, or of mind, or of perception, Po.t.thapaada is equating soul with one of the skandhakas. He is not concerned about the eternity of the soul or otherwise. In other words we are dealing here with the Satkaayad.r.s.ti, the root cause of all other false views. In rejecting the Satkaayad.r.s.ti the Buddha is not denying the existence of attaa on the basis of pa.ticcasamuppaada as he did while instructing his own disciples. He is even accepting-for the sake of argument, or we may say as a skillful means-Po.t.thapaada's point of view regarding the existence of soul or the constitution of soul, and then rejecting the suggested identity by exposing the logical inconsistencies involved in the suggestion. He is showing that the acceptance of the view that the soul is made of mind or four gross elements contradicts the other aspect of the suggestion, viz. soul is identical with perception. b) Mahaanidaanasutta and the rejection of a dii- ierent type of Satkaayad.r.s.ti (51) Mahaanidaanasutta ( 52 ) rejects a new type of Satkaayak.r.s.t.i which may be formulated as soul possessing feelings. The relevant passage is given below: "Herein, again, Aaanada, to him who affirms: 'Nay, my soul is not feeling, nor is it non- ──────────── (51) For Sanskrit parallels to different attaa concepts discussed in the Mahanidaanasutta, see, Nidanasa^myukta, C.B.Tripathi, Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften Zu Berlin, IO, 1962. (52) Diigha nikaaya, Vol.II, XV.31, p.67(PTS London, 1982), Dialogues of the Buddha Part II, p.64 (Pts, London, 1977) P.417 -sentient; my soul has feelings, it has the property of sentience '--answer should be made: -'My friend, were feelings of every kind to cease absolutely, then there being, owing to cessation thereof, no feeling whatever, could one then say: --"I myself am'?" 'No, lord, one could not.' 'Wherefore, Aananda, it follows that this aspect: -'Nay, my soul is not feel feeling, nor is it non-sentient; my soul has feelings, it has the property of sentience'-does not commend itself". Here the Buddha is teaching Aananda how to refute the heresy of Satakaayad.r.s.ti. The view that the soul is not feeling, but possesses feelings shows that the feeling is not intrinsic to attaa but external to it. It, therefore, follows that the presence of absence of feeling should not at all affect the basic nature of soul. But, as the Buddha points out, our daily experience shows that in the absence of all feelings there cannot be any I-awareness which is the very essence of attaa. So the feeling is not external to soul; soul cannot be regarded as having feelings. The accepted idea that attaa essentially means I-awareness goes against the view that attaa has feelings. The attaa heresy under discussion is concerned with the relationship existing between the soul and the skandhakas, and so falls under the category of satkaayad.r.s.ti. It is by way of expediency that the Buddha accepts I-awareness as the very core of an assumed attaa and thereby shows that the present heresy suffers from internal contradiction. It is also to be noted that the Buddha's instructions, though addressed to Aananda, is ultimately meant for the non-Buddhist ascetics. iii) The Mahaanidaanasutta and the rejection of the Ekaccasassatavaada The Mahaanidaanasutta (53) also contains passages rejecting the heresy that the soul is feeling. The relevant part of the sutta runs as follows: -"Herein, Aananda, to him who affirms' My soul is feeling'-answer should be thus made: -'My friend, feelings is of three kinds. There is happy feeling, painful feeling, and neutral feeling. Of these three feelings, look you, which do you consider your soul is?' ──────────── (53) Dialogues of the Buddha, Part II, pp.63-64; Diigha Nikaaya, Vol. II, XV.28; 29, pp.66-67 P.418 'When you feel a happy feeling you do not feel a painful feeling or a neutral feeling, you feel just a happy feeling. And when you feel a painful feeling, you do not feel a happy feeling or a neutral feeling, but just a painful feeling. And when you feel a neutral feeling, you do not feel a happy feeling or a painful feeling; you feel just a neutral feeling.' "Moreover, Aananda, happy feeling is impermanent, conditioned (sa~nkhata), the result of cause or causes, liable to perish, to pass away, to become extinct, to cease. So too the painful feeling. So too is neutral feeling. If when experiencing a happy feeling one thinks-'this is my soul'-when that same happy feeling ceases, one will also think-'my soul has departed'-So too when the feeling is painful or neutral. Thus he who say-'My soul is feeling'-regards, as his soul something which, in this present life, is impermanent, is blended of happiness and pain, and is liable to begin and end. Wherefore, Aananda, it follows that this aspect-'My soul in feeling'-does not commend itself." The passage in question rejects the view that the individual soul is feeling. The daily experience of people shows that the feeling is impermanent, a blending of happiness and pain, and subject to origination and destruction. This characterisation of feeling will be, in the main, also acceptable to the Ekaccasassatavaadins, for they as we have already noted, accepted the idea that the created is impermanent. The feeling so characterised is different from soul. The soul thus appears to be permanent, beyond origination and destruction, and experiencing unmixed happiness. It is identical with one of the skandhas. This concept of attaa is, in all its essential features, identical with that held by the logicians among the Ekaccasassatavaadins who also believed the individual soul to be eternal, and identical with one of the skandhas belonging to the sphere of mind. It is to be noted that the Buddha is denying the Ekaccasassatavaada not on the strength of the law of pa.ticcasamuppaada or any other Buddhist dogma. It is obviously because his invoking of the higher knowledge would cut no ice with the non-Buddhists. He is, on the other hand, showing that the philosophy under criticism suffers from internal contradiction, and hence untenable. He shows that the Ekaccasassatavaada concept of feeling is diametrically opposed to the Ekaccasassatavaada concept of soul, and so the view that the soul is identical with feeling p.419 is to be discarded. The Mahaanidaanasutta passage supports our conclusion that the Buddha also taught his disciples how to defeat the upholders of the attaa heresy in debate. Here the Buddha is teaching Aananda how to refute the view of the Ekaccasassatavaadins. In other words his teaching is ultimately meant for the followers of the Ekaccasassatavaada. iv) The mahaanidaanasutta rejects an atypical attaa heresy: In the Mahaanidaanasutta (54) we come across a heresy which does not conform to any of the types mentioned before. The relevant passage recording a negative formulation the heresy is given below:- "Herein, Aananda, to him who affirms: 'Nay, my soul is not feeling, my soul is not sentient' - answer should thus be given " 'My friend, where there is no feeling of anything, can you there say: 'I am?' 'You cannot, Lord,' 'Wherefore, Aananda, it follows that this aspect: 'Nay, my soul is not feeling, my soul is not sentient'-does not commend itself." The view that the individual soul is not feeling and sentient is rejected because there cannot be any aareness of 'I' without feeling and sentience. Hence there cannot be any soul without feeling and sentience. Here the criticism is based on the assumption of 'I-awareness' as the essence of the individual soul. The proposition admits of the existence of an individual soul, asserts the soul's difference from feeling and sentience, and is silent about the question whether the individual soul is eternal or not. This is now type of attaa heresy which is neither 'Saa'svatavaada nor Ucchedavaada. Strictly speaking this negative formulation is not even all illustration of Satkaayard.r.s.t.ti, as it denies instead of affirming, the relationship existing between the soul and the skandhas. Against our contention one may argue that the formulation-attaa is not feeling -was merely used to imply that the soul is identical with some other skandha. In this case this implication should be treated as the main proposition, which is different from the given proposition. If this were so, the Buddhist criticism ──────────── (54) Dialogues, Part 11, p.64; Diigha Nikaaya Vol.II, XV.30,p.67 P.420 would have been directed against a proposition asserting the identity of soul with skandhaka and not against the formulation of the soul not being feeling. But as this is not the case, we have to take the given proposition as the main proposition. Thought the negative formulation states that the individual soul is not the same as feeling, it should not be interpreted to mean that the soul is not connected with any of the five skandhas. For the Sa^myutta Nikaaya passage quoted above shows that the negative formulation of this type is also the result of the Satkaaya.r.s.ti. To sum up, the attaa concepts held by the followers of the 'Saa'svatavaada, Ekaccasassatavaada, Ucchedavaada, and Satkaayad.r.s.tti mainly have been criticised and rejected in the Nikaayas and Aagamas. None of these concepts are identical with the Upani.sadic Aatman-Brahman. Except the Ucchedavaada, all other concepts regarding attaa have been criticised in two defferent ways. When the criticisms rejecting the attaa heresies were addressed to his own disciples, the Buddha referred to his more extensive knowledge that could see farther into the past and future lives of the beings, and his superior knowledge of the law dependent origination (Pa.ticcasamuppaada). But when the criticisms were meant for the non-Buddhist ascetics all references to these two types of knowledge were avoided. The Buddha by way of expediency makes use of a part of the opponent's proposition for the sake of further argumentation, and thereby lays bare the internal contradictions involved in the proposition. This method of reductio ad absurdum which the Buddha introduced, was later applied by Naagaarjuna with great success. The Ucchedavaada was criticised only on the basis of the Buddha's extensive knowledge and superior knowledge but not on logical grounds, as the Ucchedavaada philosophy does not suffer from any logical inconsistencies. V We have shown that the early Buddhist scripture rejected any notion of attaa which was either identical with the skandhas or dependent on them for its very existence. The Buddha specially took great paints to discard the 'Saa'svatavaadins and the Ucchedavaadins who preached the philosophy of attaa and nirattaa respectively. The Buddhists were aware of this fact and gave expression to it in P.421 canonical and non-canonical texts. We will cite a few quotations from the Buddhist texts in support of our view. In the Du.t.tha.t.thakasutta (No.8) of the Suttanipaata we read the following verse; (55) "attam nirattam na hi tassa a.t.thi adhosi se di.t.thimidha sabbaa" Here the belief in attaa and nirattaa are counted among the false views (di.t.thi) which a follower of the Buddha has given up. Again the following two verses from Lalitavistara (56) and Madhyamikakaarikaa (57) while confirming the Buddhist rejection of both attaa and nirattaa give some extra information regarding these heresies: i) astinaastivinirumktamaatmyanairaatmyavarjitam prak.rtyaa jaatinirde'sam dharmacakram ihocyate. ii) astiiti 'saa'svatagraaho nastiityucchedaa- dar'sanam tasmaadastivanaastitve naa'sriyeta vicak.sana. From the verses quoted above it is evident that the existence of an eternal indireidual soul (attaa0 was preached in the philosophy of the 'Saa'svatavaada and term 'asti' in its vocabulary did not convey the ordinary meaning of mere existence but acquired the special sense of eternal existence. On the other hand the Ucchedavaada which preached the philosophy of nirattaa (nairaatmya), coined the term'nasti' to signify simultaneous annihilation of the temporarily existing attaa and the physical body. It is in these special senses that the Pali Buddhist texts use these two terms 'asti' and 'nasti' while recording the dialogues between the Buddha and the non-Buddhist ascetics. Any lack of awareness of the special imports of 'asti' and 'naasti' may result in drawing wrong conclusions from such dialogues. As the ego-centricity and absolute dependence on the Skandakas-the two ──────────── (55) PTS, London, 1913; also see, The Group of Discourses, II(PTS, London, 1992) p.304 (56) Leffman, Lalitavistara, p.426 (57) Maadhyamikakaarikaa, 15.10 P.422 hallmarks of the concept of attaa-can be no means by associated with the Upani.sadic Aatman-Brahman, it is but natural that the Nikaaya criticisms do not contain any reference to the Upani.sadic concept. The post-canonical early Buddhist texts also never confused attaa with the Aatman-Brahman of the Upani.sads. In the Vajracchedikaa Praj~naapaaramitaa (58) aatman is used together with such terms as jiiva, sattva and pudgala. All these terms are put in the same category and are used to denote different aspects of the same ego-centric entity. 'Sacet Bodhisattvasya sattva sa.mj~naa pravarteta na sa bodhisattva iti vaktavya. Tat kasya hetoh? na sa Subhuute bodhisattvo vaktavyo yasya aatma-sa.mj~naa pravarteta, sattva-sa.mj~naa vaa jiivasa.mj~naa vaa pudgala-sa.mj~naa va pravarteta'.'If in a Bodhisattva the perception of a being should take place, then he could not be called a Bodhisattva. And why? He is not to be called a Bodhisattva in whom the perception of a soul, or a being, or a living being, or a person would take place'. (59) Similary in the early Maadhyamika literature we read:'Ko 'yam aatmaa yo 'ha^nkaaravi.saya.h', which may be translated as follows: What is this aatman that is the domain of ego? (60) Here aatman(Pali: attaa) is characterised by aha^nkaara. In this context we may refer to the definition of 'upadhi' in sopadhi'se.sanirvaa.nam as given by Candrakiirti(61) in the Prasannapadaa: tatra upadhiyate asminn aatmasneha ity upadhi.h, upadhi 'sabdenaatmapraj~napti-nimittaa.h pa~ncop- aadaanaskandhaa ucyante'. Here the concept of aatmaa is held to be caused by the five aggregates of attachment. The same idea is expressed by Buddhaghosa (62) while defining 'attabhaava'. 'Attabhaavo vuccanti sariiram. Khandha-pa~ncakam eva vaa, tam upaadaaya pa~n~natti-matta sabhaavato'. Conze translates: 'Personal existence means the body, or the five Skandhas together, because dependent on them this mere concept cones about.' (63) Thus it is clear that these early Buddhist texts while discussing the concept of attaa never thought about the Upani.sadic Aatman, but remained faithful to the Nikaaya ──────────── (58) Vajracchedikaa Praj~naapaaramitaa (E.Conze, Rome, Is.M.E.O. 1957)p.29 (59) Also see, ibid.pp.66-67 (60) Poussin, Muula-Madhyamaka-Kaarikaas, Ch.18, p.340 (61) Conze, ibid. p.94;Poussin, ibid. p.519-520 (62) Visuddhimagga (h.c.Warren, 1950) IX,54 (63) Vajracchedikaa Praj~naapaaramitaa, p.100 P.423 characteristics of attaa, viz. the ego-centricity and its invariable relationship with the skandhas. This point has been clearly stated by Vasubandhu. In his Vi.m'satikaa-v.rtti Vasubandhu(64) states: 'Yo baalair dharmaanaam svabhavo graahyagraahakadi.h parikalpitas tena parikalpitenaatmanaa te.saam nairaatmyam, na tv anabhilaapyenaatmanaa yo buddhaanaam vi.saya.h 'It is because of that imaginary aatman which the ignorant people think to the things' self-being consisting of subject and object etc., that the things are devoid of aatman, not because of the ineffable Aatman which is the domain of the Buddhas'. The attaa rejected by the Bhaddhas is "aha^nkaara-vi.saya.h" whereas the ineffable Upani.sadic Aatman is 'buddhaanaam vi.saya.h'. ──────────── (64) Vi.msatikaa-v.rtti(Ed. S.Levi, paris. 1925)p.6 Key words : 1.Attaa 2.Nirattaa 3.Anattaa 4.Upani.sad P.424     提要   本文共分五節,討論外道持的 attaa( 我 )觀究竟如何 ,佛教又如何用 anttaa (無我 )論來破它。   第一節引《阿含》和《尼柯耶》,肯定在有為界與無為 界都沒 attaa,它只不過是想像的產品。   第二節介紹近代學者對 attaa 一詞函義的種種看法。 其中只有 Conze 一人發現,佛教講的 attaa 和數論所謂的 puru.sa 有相似處。其他所有思考過此一問題的學者或許 由於 attaa、aatman 二詞對等,單單關心 attaa 與奧義書 aatman 有何關聯,而未經系統的研究,確信二者之間有關 係。此一觀念顯然有必要重新評估。本節則提出較客觀、適 當的研究方法。   第三節簡要敘述持 attaa 見的常論者和持 nirattaa 見的斷論者主要思想。   第四節分析佛教如何破 attaa 的信念。在反駁 attaa 的基礎上分別擬構出常論者和斷論者所持的論點,並發現佛 教用三種推理方式來破 attaa。尤其破常見及身見者的方式 顯示辯論的兩種重要特色: 一、以揭發對方說法內在矛盾來 駁斥。這個方法後來的大乘佛教用得非常成功。二、先接受 對方部分說法,把它當做進一步顯示該說法謬誤的基礎。這 或許可以看做大乘教所推崇的 [ 方便 ]。   第五節指出,佛陀提 anattaa 的中道是針對常論者和 斷論者的極端見解。同時證明常論、斷論所謂 attaa,並非 奧義書的 aatman。