p. 221 In a well-known article(1) Dr. Satis Chandra Vidyabhusana expressed the view that Uddyotakara, the famous Nyaya commentator, knew the Vadanyaya of Dharmakirti which he cited in his Nyayavarttika on i, 1, 33 as Vadavidhi. He reinforced this view by holding that Uddyotakara knew also the vadavidhanatika, which he cites (on i,1, 33 and 41) in respect of the definition of paksa and vada respectively, and that the Tibetan translation of the vadanyayatika of Vinitadeva proves to contain passages substantially identical with those cited by Uddyotakara. The result of this argument is, of course, important in that it establishes, when taken in conjunction with the fact that Uddyotakara seems to be known to Dharmakirti, the contemporaneity of the two writers, who may be referred to in immediate proximity in a pun of Subandhu's in his Vasavadatta.(2) To this view exception is taken in an interesting articles(3) by H.R. Rangaswamy Iyengar, who contends that the reference to the Vadavidhi is to a work by the well-known Vasubandhu. He holds that the difference of name, Vadavidhi and Vadanyaya, tells strongly against the identification, but this can hardly be deemed a conclusive ground; there are far too many cases known in which works bear more than one title, and apart from that, even in modern days of libraries and easy access to titles, errors in citation of books by name are not rare. Nor can we say that the definition of pratijna cited from the Vadavidhi "bears only a semblance of similarity to that given by Dharmakirti in his Vadanyaya." As the author himself proceeds to slow, a literal rendering of the Tibetan gives us the words pratijna ca sadhyabhidhanat which ---------------------- 1. JRAS., 1914, PP. 601-6. 2. Keith, JRAS., 1914, pp. 1102 f. 3. JBORS, xii. 587-91. p. 222 for all purposes is identical with the sadhyabhidhanam pratijna of the citation from the Vadavidhi. It appears, therefore, that the attempt to disprove the reference to the Vadanyaya is inadequate. Mr. Iyengar adduces as a further argument the fact that on this identification of the Vadavidhi, the Vadavidhanatika must be identified with the work of Vinitadeva, which is objectionable on the score of the late date of that author. He seems not to know that Dr. Satis Chandra Vidyabhusana definitely accepted this identification and supported it by citation of the Tibetan renderings in the Vadanyayatika; this is doubtless due to the fact that this point is passed over in the History of Indian Logic and is only set out in the article in the Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society. As a matter of fact, we are not in a position definitely to determine the date of Vinitadeva from any external evidence; that brought forward in the History of Indian Logic(p.320) claims no special value, and before the theory of the use of Vinitadeva by Uddyotakara can be definitely disposed of, it will be necessary to deal with the two citations which Dr. Vidyabhusana claimed to identify. It must be added that it can hardly be doubted that the Vadavidh anatika must be intended to be a comment on the Vadavidhi, a point which illustrates the fact that slight variants of name without essential change of sense may be taken for legitimate in Indian works. Mr. Iyenger's own view would see in the Vadavidhi a work of Vasbandhu; on the question of the Vadavidhanatika he is silent, though obviously it is not advisable to seek to .separate the two issues; his position would have been enormously strengthened had he been able to point to a commentary on the Vadavidhi of Vasubandhu which was referred to by Uddyotakara. Moreover it must be admitted that, as the author very fairly points out, the Tibetan title of the work which he has adduced would normally and properly be rendered Vadasiddhi, which is by no means the same as p. 223 Vadavidhi, and that the rendering Vadavidhi rests on the translation of the Chinese title Ronki of a work of Vasubandhu as Vadavidhi. But, this apart, the evidence on which the claim is made that Vasubandhu's work is referred to is wholly indirect. Mr. Iyengar has not adduced any definition of pratijna ascribed to Vasubandhu's Vadavidhi (Vadasiddhi); on the contrary, all that he can point out is that Uddyotakara criticises two definitions of pratyaksa and anumana, which are apparently the same as those criticised by Dignaga in his Pramanasamuccaya (to judge from the Tibetan version), and the comment on that work ascribes them to the Vadavidhi, without naming any author. On the other hand, Vacaspati in the case of the definition of pratyaksa ascribes it to Vasubandhu. The argument, therefore, is: Uddyotakara cites a definition of pratijna from a Vadavidhi; he deals with definitions of pratyaksa and anumana, which appear apparently in the same shape in the Tibetan version of the Pramanasamuccaya and by its comment are ascribed to a Vadasiddhi or possibly Vadavidhi, and one of these definitions is definitely ascribed to Vasubandhu by Vacaspati; therefore "we can safely conclude" that the Vadavidhi referred to by Uddyotakara is the work of Vasubandhu. There are, it is clear, far too many gaps in this reasoning, and nothing convincing can be adduced unless and until the question of the Vadavidhanatika is faced at the same time. When we consider that text difficulties do not lessen. The theory of Dr.Vidyabhusana is clear, and is supported by the passages which he cites from the Vadanyayatika, which has definitions of paksa and of vada corresponding to those ascribed absolutely clearly in the first case, and with much probability in the second, to the Vadavidhanatika. Other authorities do not recognise that the second reference is to that work, but unquestionably, as will be shown below, that is a legitimate inference from the discussion, and it is very greatly strengthened by the coincidence of the occurrence p. 224 of the passage in the Vadanyayatika. As regards the first passage, there is an interesting suggestion by Dr. Randle in his Fragments from Dinnaga that the author may be Dignaga; unfortunately he does not appear to know the article in the Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society. The position would then be that Vasubandhu wrote the Vadavidhi, and that Dignaga corrected it in the Vadavidhanatika, and this view would, of course, have the great advantage over that of Mr. Iyengar in that it would solve the whole problem and not leave it but half answered. It is, therefore, desirable to submit this theory to a critical investigation as far as our scanty sources permit. There is, of course, one strong objection to any such view, viz., the absence of any evidence of the writing by Dignaga of a commentary on the Vadavidhi of Vasubandhu, assuming that Vasubandhu did write a treatise of that name. This point is not absolutely decisive, but it prevents us feeling any certainty regarding the proposed explanation, even if other matters did not tell against it. Nor is the rest of the evidence satisfactory. Dr. Ganganath Jha(1) holds that the Vadavidhi referred to by Uddyotakara is a work of Subandhu, and he finds another reference to it in the Nyayavarttika (p.157, line l7) by reading there sastratvena ca vadavidhanam abhyupagamyate for the vadabhidhanam of the recorded text. The amendment may be tempting, but it is clearly illegitimate, for as Dr. Randle (p.55, n.2) admits, the accepted text makes sense, and, it may be added, the corruption supposed has no obvious explanation, so that on any sound principle of textual criticism this passage must be ignored in this connection. The ground for ascribing the Vadavidhi to Subandhu is thus gravely impugned, for its justification rested(1) on the fact that Vacaspati (p.218, line 9) ascribes the definition of vada given by Uddyotakara (p.151, line 20) to Subandhu ( Saubandhavam laksanam) and (2) on the amendment --------------------- 1. See his translation, i, 441 and 454 notes, p. 225 of vadabhidhanam to vadavidhanam. If this conjecture be laid aside, as it must properly be, the ascription to Subandhu of the Vadavidhi is purely conjectural. Morever, as against Dr. Ganganath Jha's view must be set the fact that he conjectures(1) that the definition of paksa given in the Nyayavarttika (p.116, line 14) as yah sadhayitum istah is that of Subandhu, But the Vadavidhanatika, as cited by Uddyotakara, is absolutely clear in indicating that the word svayam was contained in the definition which it defended, and, therefore , it is most improbable that Subandhu was the author of the Vadavidhi, if Dr. Ganganath Jha's ascription of the definition without svayam to him is correct. It must be added that there seems no ground for the ascription. But one fact emerges from this mass of conjectures. Vacaspati definitely refers to Subandhu the definition of vada cited anonymously in Uddyotakara (p.151), but by Dr. Vidyabhusana ascribed to the Vadavidhanatika and identified with a passage in the Vadanyayatika in its Tibetan rendering. On this identification one doubt presents itself, which should be noted; Uddyotakara (p.124, line 9) has an almost identical definition of vada, in which svaparapaksasiddhyasiddhyartham in p.151 is replaced by svaparapaksayoh siddhyasiddhyartham. It is just possible that the Tibetan rendering could be made applicable to this definition of p. 124 as opposed to that of p.151, and it may be argued that the occurrence of the phrase at p.124, in comparatively close proximity to the citation of the Vadavidhanatika at p. 120, is in favour of the view that the citation at p. 124 rather than that at p.151 is from that work. However that may be, and it may be presumed that Dr. Vidyabhusana decided against this possiblity, though he does not mention the point, there remains the question of who Subandhu was. Both Dr. Ganganath Jha(2) and Dr. Vidyabhusana(3) identify him ---------------------- 1. i, 331. 2. i, 441; but compare i, 394. 3. History of Indian Logic; p.128. p. 226 with Vasubandhu, the former, it is true, with some hesitation. Dr. Randle(l) holds that the reasonable supposition is that "in these passages (i.e. those in which Saubandhavam laksanam is referred to) Vacaspati abbreviates Vasubandhu to Subandhu, just as he invariably speaks of Dharmakirti as Kirti". The parallelism is not complete, for admittedly Vacaspati (p.99, line 13) cites as Vasubandhavam pratyaksa laksanam the definition of pratyakas given in the Nyayavarttika (p.42, line 15), and the question, therefore, arises why in certain cases he should use an abbreviated form. But far more serious is the character of the abbreviated form. That Kirti should be used for Dharmakirti, or Hari for Bhartrhari, or Simha for Vikramasimha or Gupta for Candragupta, and so forth is obvious and natural, but that without reason a man's name should be reduced from Vasubandhu to Subandhu is extremely hard to credit, and indeed may be dismissed as out of the question. It remains only for those who hold this view to suggest not an abbreviation but a variant name, and it is, to be frank, extremely implausible to urge that the same author should in the same work use the regular name of a famous author, and also a name which never is elsewhere applied to him, and which, it must be added, is not equivalent in sense. It must, accordingly, in my opinion be admitted that the evidence is lamentably inadequate to overthrow the view of Dr. Vidyabhusana. Unquestionably on chronological grounds there is some reason to doubt the use by Uddyotakara of Vinitadeva, but, if the matter is to be established in any other sense than that adopted by Dr. Vidyabhusana, new evidence must be adduced, and this note has been written in order to indicate the lacuna in the existing evidence. It is hardly necessary to add that no confirmation of the use of Subandhu for Vasubandhu is to be found in Vamana's Kavyalamkarasutravrtti (iii, 2, 2). If we wish to find Vasubandhu, ---------------------- 1. Fragments from Dinnaga, p.26. p. 227 there we have simply to alter the ca before Subandhu into va, whereas no such correction is possible in any of the passages where Vacaspati refers to Subandhu(l) or Saubandhavam laksanam. It may further be concluded that we have no adequate evidence for the identification of Subandhu with Vasubandhu, a result which is of importance because, apart from this identification, Vasubandhu, according to our present knowledge plays a much less prominent part in the early history of Buddhist logic than would be the case if we could securely(2) assign to him the Vadavidhi, the definition of vada, and pratijna, and assume that he was a predecessor of Dignaga in his criticism of the views of proposition, reason and exemplification given in the Nyayasutra. All these things may be true, but for the time being they are conjectures, which do not square with the scanty evidence actually available. We do know his definition of perception, and frankly it cannot be said to reveal him as a profound logician. Dignaga seems to record that he did not specialise in this topic, though he may largely have inspired that acute logician. Professor Stcherbatsky's suggestion(3) that he may have adumbrated the doctrine of the affinity of perception to inference, and so have evoked the polemic of the Nyayasutra (ii, 1, 30), can hardly be regarded as convincing; assuming that the passage in question formed part of the original text, there is nothing whatever to induce us to fix on the exact form of the doctrine against which the Nyaya, contended. There was unquestionably in ancient India a vast activity of thought which is only hinted at in the tantalising brevity and obscurity of the Sutras of the philosophic schools, and me run serious risks of misconstruing the facts if we seek unduly to simplify the history of thought. ---------------------- 1. p. 205, line 26 2. Fragments from Dinnaga, pp.27, 28. 3. La theorie de la connaissance et de la logique chex les Bouddhistes tardifs, p.197, n.3. For Dignaga's view, ibid., p. 2,