Discussion of the Buddhist Doctrines of Momentariness and Subjective Idealism in the Nyaya-sutras

BY Jwala Prasad
Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society
1930, pp.31-39



p. 31 There is a difference of opinion among scholars as regards the exact significance of such Nyaya-sutras as are supposed to refer to the doctrines of the Madhyamika and the Yogacara schools of Buddhism. It has also been suggested that probably some of these sutras have been interpolated later on, possibly by Vatsyayana--the author of the Nyaya-bhasya. After making a careful study of the sutras in question, however, I have come to the conclusion that some of them, in any case, do not refer to the Buddhist doctrines at all, and form a natural and quite an integral part of the particular sections in which they occur, and that the theory which regards them as later interpolations is not justifiable. First I propose to consider one such section of the Nyayasutras, viz. iii, 2, 10, to iii, 2, 18, which, according to all the commentators beginning with Vatsyayana, is supposed to contain a refutation of the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness (ksanika-vada). According to Vidyabhusana these sutras refer to the doctrine of momentariness, as found in the Lankavatara-sutra, chap. vi; and he also holds that Sutra, iii, 2, 10, which forms the main basis for holding this view, has probably been interpolated by Vatsyayana.(1) Now improbable as it might appear that none of the many distinguished commentators should have been able to see the points which I am going to raise against this time-honoured view, I cannot help thinking that this particular section does not refer to the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness at all, and that the commentators have simply been carried away by the notions suggested by the term "ksanikatvad" in Sutra, iii, 2, 10. Some of the modern 1. Vidyabhugana, History of Indian Logic, pp. 120, 121. Sutra,a, iii, 2, 10,. being Sphatike 'py aparaparo- tpatteh ksanikatvad vyaktinnam ahetuh. p. 32 scholars have noticed the abruptness and superfluousness of introducing such a topic in the middle of an altogether different discussion, and have, hence, suggested the theory of interpolation. I shall try presently, however, to show that the Sutras, iii, 2, 1, to iii, 2, 17, form one whole section dealing with the transitory nature of cognition (buddhi), and that the discussion contained in it refers only to the Samkhya view, according to which the buddhi is a permanent and abiding faculty. That these sutras were once looked upon as forming one section and as referring to the topic of the non-permanence of buddhi will appear from the concluding section of the Nyaya-bhasya on Sutra, iii, 2, 17-iti upapannam anitya buddhir iti "thus it is proved that buddhi is non-eternal". Vardhamana had noticed this point about the Bhasya, but he himself regarded these sutras as forming an altogether different section. He says: "Some people have held that this is only a part, and continuation, of the fore-going section, and should not be treated as a separate section; specially because the Bhasya, at the end of the present section, concludes with the words: 'Thus it is proved that buddhi is non-eternal,' from which it is clear that the Bhasya takes the whole as one section dealing with the non-eternality of buddhi. But the fact of the matter is that the subject- matter of the present section is totally different..."(1) The Tatparya and the Parisuddhi simply explain away this introduction of a discussion of the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness into this section. As has already been pointed out, the chief ground for holding that this section refers to the Buddhist doctrine of ksanika-vada is to be found in the language of Sutra, iii, 2, l0--sphatike 'py aparaparotpatteh ksanikatvad vyaktinam ahetuh. Now this sutra should normally be regarded as an answer (uttara-paksa) to one of the preceding sutras, which represent the opponent's view (purva-paksa) from the point of view of the Samkhya, viz. sphatikanyatva- bhimanavat tadanyatvabhimanah "there is a false notion 1. Indian Thought, x, p. 313. p. 33 of its being different, like that with regard to the difference pertaining to a rock-crystal"; that is to say, the Samkhya opponent says that buddhi, though really one, appears to be diverse, just like a rock-crystal, which also appears to be different because of the reflections of the different colours upon it. It will appear that the Nyaya-suci-nibandha and the commentators regard this sutra as the end of the section dealing with the non-eternality of buddhi "iti navabhih sutrair buddhy-anityata-prakaranam"; and, according to them, an altogether new section begins with the Sutra sphatike ''py, etc., which, according to all the commentators, contains an objection to the doctrine of permanence of things from the point of view of the Buddhist, who holds the doctrine of momentariness. The sutra has been translated thus: "In the rock-crystal also, one (rock-crystal) being produced after another, since all the individual things are momentary, there is to be found no reason." The following seven sutras are then supposed to contain a discussion of the doctrine of momentariness between the Buddhist and the Nyaya philosopher. Now I cannot help thinking that this view is the most absurd to hold, and it is so for the following reasons:-- 1. It is very unusual and unnatural that at the end of a discussion the author of the Nyaya-sutras should stop with a sutra representing the opponent's view (purva-paksa) and not finish with an answer establishing his own view (uttara-paksa). 2. It would be curious that the author of the Nyaya- sutras, while trying to establish the non- eternality of buddhi as against the Samkhya philosopher, should leave him and the subject under discussion alone, and abruptly usher in a Buddhist, apparently against the Samkhya first, make him say something which is distinctly against the Nyaya view, and then begin to measure swords with him. 3. The Sutras, iii, 2, 10 to iii, 2, 18 are evidently a discussion of the Samkhya view of cause and effect rather than of the p. 34 Buddhist doctrine of momentariness. This is clear from the example of the production of curd out of milk, and from the fact that as the Sutra "na payasah parinamah gunantara-pradur-bhavad" could not be explained in terms of a discussion between a Nyaya philosopher and the Buddhist, the Bhasya introduces it with the observation: atra kascit pariharam aha "here someone has offered the following refutation"; and the Vrtti actually says: saugatamate samkhyadusanam upanyasati "the author points out a defect in the Buddhist doctrine from the point of view of the Samkhya". A study of the sutras in question will easily show that the sutra is not an answer to the Buddhist view, which is, in fact, to be found in none of the sutras in this section, but to the Nyaya view that the effect is different from the cause; for it is said in this sutra that milk, while it becomes curd, is only transformed by the appearance of different qualities. Further, would it not be a curious procedure again that the Nyaya philosopher should introduce a Samkhya, with a view different from his own, to meet his opponent, who, this time, is the Buddhist? The fact is that a hopeless confusion has been created by the assumption that the Sutra sphatike py, etc., has reference to the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness,(l) simply because 1. For considerations of space it is impossible to consider here every sutra in this section, but the main arguments given above should be sufficient to show that the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness is not the theme of these sutras. It is evident that it is the term ksanikatvad in the sutra which has suggested the presence of this doctrine here; but it is to be noted that ksanika and its derivatives are quite normally used to denote simply "momentary" as apart from the technical sense of the term as found in the Buddhist metaphysics. A very happy example of the use of the word, and that, too, in order to express the momentary nature of cognition (buddhi), which forms the subject of discussion in the present context also, is to be found in the Sabara-bhasya under Mimamsa-sutra, i, 1, 5, where it is said: arthavisaya hi pratyaksa-buddhih, buddhy-antara- visaya; ksanika hi sa, na buddhy-antara-kalam- avasthasyate. Another text of the Sloka-varttika under Mimamsa-sutra, i, 1, 4, and the Kasika on the same provide another example of the use of this term in the same kind of context. Speaking about buddhi, the Varttica says: na hi sa ksanam-apy-aste jayate va pramatmakam(i, iv, 54); and the Kasika explains: kintu nendriyadivaj jata sati buddhih ksanamatram apy aste, etc. p. 35 it happens to contain the term ksanikatvad. I shall presently offer my own explanation of the sutra, and show that the Sutras, iii, 2, 1, to iii, 2, 17, form one continuous section dealing with the non-eternality of buddhi, as against the Samkhya view that it is eternal. After the Samkhya explanation of the non-simultaneity of cognitions and the non-recognition of an object, as given in the Sutras, iii, 2, 6, and 7, has been refuted by the Nyaya philosopher by means of the assertion contained in the Sutra, iii, 2, 8, na gatyabhavat, that the explanation given by the Samkhya cannot be true because, according to them, there is no motion in buddhi, the follower of the Samkhya says in Sutra, iii, 2, 9 that there is only a semblance of difference (and therefore of diversity) in cognitions like that to be found in the case of a rock-crystal (which, although one, appears to be different according to the reflections on it). After this, I hold that the assertion hetv-abhavad, which has been regarded as a Nyaya-sutra by some, and as only a part of the Bhasya by others, is really a Nyaya-sutra forming the uttara-paksa along with the next three sutras, viz. sphatike ''py, etc. In the Sutra, na hetv- abhavad, it is said that there is no proof that buddhi is like a rock-crystal (it is simply an illustration which you give), and in the next sutra then, sphatike 'py aparaparotpatteh ksanikatvad uyaktinam ahetuh, it is further maintained that even the case of a crystal is not in point, since, in it also, because the reflections are produced one after another, the individual reflections are momentary, the main object being to emphasize the fact that the diversity of reflections in a crystal is not a case of semblance, but of real production by the objects reflected into it. The term "api" in sphatike 'py is very significant, and is indicative of the fact that this sutra is a development of an argument begun in a previous sutra, and this we actually find in the Sutra, na hetv-abhavad. The next two sutras also represent the uttara-paksa: In the Sutra, niyamahetv-abhavad yatha-darsanam abhyanujna it is p. 36 said that as there is no reason to support a universal rule (with regard to the permanence or transitoriness of objects), we can admit (the truth or falsity of this character about things) only in accordance with our experience; since, according to the Nyaya-sutras, neither are all the objects necessarily permanent, nor are they necessarily transitory.(1) But, it is pointed out in the next Sutta, notypatti-vinasa- karaopalabdheh, that in this particular case, it is not right to say that buddhi is permanent, because the causes of the production and destruction of cognitions can be perceived.(2) This leads to a discussion of the nature of production by means of the example of curd and milk, which discussion also is evidently one between a follower of the Samkhya and a Nyaya philosopher. It is rather strange that Vidyabhusana should see in the Sutra sphatike 'py, etc., an echo of the doctrine of momentariness as found in the Lankavatara-sutra, chap. vi,(3) when, evidently, the doctrine as defined in this work shows a distinct divergence from the view about the production of individuals contained in the Nyaya-sutra in question. According to Vidyabhusana's own quotation and its translation,(4) the author of the Lankavatara-sutra says, "A momentary thing is that which is inactive, distinct in itself, and not liable to cessation. By calling things momentary I mean that they are not produced; I do not, O fools! say that they are destroyed after being produced."(5) This statement clearly shows that the doctrine of momentariness, as explained here, simply means change, and not production and destruction of things every moment; while in the 1. Cf. Nyaya-sutra, iv, 1, 28. 2. Cf. Ns., iii, 2, 24: "Inasmuch as cognition is recognized as non-as eternal, its destruction proceeds from another cognition, just like sound." 3. History of Indian Logic, p.121.p. 121. 4. History of Indian Logic, p. 246. Nirvyaparam ksanikam viviktam ksayavarjitam, Anutpattim ca dharmanam ksanikartham vadamy-aham, Utpattyanantaram bhangam na vai desemi balisah. p. 37 Nyaya-sutra under consideration there is a distinct mention of the production of individuals one after another--apara- parotpatteh. It will appear that the doctrine that all things are non-eternal, since they have the character of being produced and destroyed, is considered by the author of the Nyaya-sutras in another section beginning with the Sutra, iv, 1, 25, sarvam anityam utpatti-vinasa-dharmakatvat, and that various doctrines relating to eternality, non-eternality and change are dealt with in the Fourth Book of the Nyaya- sutras. Hence the doctrine of momentariness, instead of being introduced in Book III, 2, in the middle of a discussion irrelevant to the subject from the Nyaya point of view, could have been easily introduced in the Fourth Book; and, in fact, the doctrine of non-eternality as found in that Book is not very different from the doctrine of momentariness. Further, it must be remembered that it is the complete destruction and the fresh production of all individual things which the author of the Nyaya-sutras objects to. He does admit non-eternality in the case of some kinds of existence, for example, in the case of cognitions themselves. The other section of the Nyaya-sutras which I propose to consider here is that which consists of Sutra, iv, 2, 26, and the following sutras. According to some, it refers to the Buddhist doctrine of subjective idealism (vijnana-vada), while according to others, it contains a discussion of the philosophy of the Madhyamika School (Sunya-vada). Vidyabhusana holds that Sutra, iv, 2, 26, and the next are later interpolations, and refer to the doctrine of vijnana-vada as found in the Lankavatara-sutra, chaps. ii and xi.(l) The view that these sutras refer to the vijnana-vada has been questioned and refuted by Jacobi as against Stcherbatsky, who held this view on the authority of Vacaspati Misra.(2) Sutra, iv, 2, 26, which is the most important in this section, is: buddhya vivecanat tu bhavanam yathatmyanupalabdhis tantvapakarsane 1. History of Indian Logic, p. 120. 2. Journal of the American Oriental Society, xxxi (1911). p. 38 patasadbhavanupalabdhivat tadanupalabdhih, and an examination of the language of the sutra will show that it certainly does not refer to the doctrine that things cannot be conceived to exist apart from the ideas of them. I shall also presently show that the sutra does not refer to the doctrine of Sunya-vada either, as Jacobi holds. A faithful translation of the sutra will indicate what it actually means. It may be rendered thus: "And by means of an analysis by intellect (buddhya vivecanat tu), the true nature of existent things is not cognized (bhavanam yathatmyanupalabdhih); they cannot be cognized, just as the existence of cloth is not cognized after the threads have been separated from one another." It will appear that Vidyabhusana's translation of the sutra, viz. "Things, some say, do not possess a reality if they are separated from our thoughts, just as there is no reality in a web separated from its threads, "(1) is evidently not correct. "buddhya vivecanat'' certainly does not mean here "separated from our thoughts",and "bhavanam yathatmyanupalabdhih" only means "the non-cognition of the true nature of things". The example of threads and cloth clearly shows that what is meant to be asserted in the sutra is that the true nature of the whole cannot be known by analyzing it into parts, which is a distinctly Nyaya view about the nature of the whole. Further, the particle tu in "buddhya vivecanat tu" indicates that the assertion in the sutra is a development of some argument that has gone before; and this is to be found in the preceding sutra, anavasthakaritvad, etc. Thus it will appear that the Sutra, iv, 2, 26, along with iv, 2, 25, instead. of representing the Buddhist view, forms the Nyaya answer (uttara-paksa) to the opponent's view (purva-paksa) contained in Nyaya-sutras, iv, 2, 23 and 24, in which it is said that an atom is not an indivisible whole but an aggregate of infinite parts. In defence of the doctrine of indivisibility of atoms it is said firstly, in iv, 2, 25, that a denial of the doctrine will lead to a regress ad infinitum, and secondly, in case it be said that 1. Nyaya-sutras (Sacred Books of the Hindus), p. 133. p. 39 an atom can be understood only as something made of parts, it is asserted in iv, 2, 26, that the nature of the whole cannot be known by analyzing it into its parts.(l) Then the following two sutras, iv, 2, 27, and iv, 2, 28, again form the purva-paksa. In the first of these vyahatatvad ahetuh, it is said that what has been asserted about the nature of the whole is no ground, because it is vitiated by contradiction; the meaning being that it is contradictory to say that the whole cannot be known by the cognition of its parts; and in the second of these tadasrayatvad aprthag-grahanam, it is further said that the whole is not known apart from its parts, for its existence depends upon them. Then the next sutra, pramanatas carthapratipatteh, represents the uttara-paksa, and asserts that an object is proved to exist, or is known by means of a pramana, that is to say, an object as a whole is known by means of the various pramanas; and this leads to a discussion in the following sutras on the validity and limitations of the pramanas.. It will appear thus that the whole section contains a discussion on the nature of the whole in its relation to the parts, and that Sutra, iv, 2, 26 simply emphasizes the Nyaya view that the true nature of the whole is known independently of its parts, and not by an analysis of its parts, or rather by analyzing it away into its parts. The explanation of such forced interpretations of the Nyaya-sutras as have been discussed above is to be found in the fact that the commentators were too anxious to make use of anything that they could get hold of in the language of the sutras in order to refute the Buddhist doctrines, which were ever pressing upon them, to pause and consider how far they were justified in doing so. 1. Compare the arguments contained in Sutras, iv, 2,7, to iv, 2, 15, especially the opponent's view in iv, 2, 14, where it is said that the perception of things would be possible, just like the perception of a mass of heir by a person of dim vision.