Ethics in Early Buddhism

Reviewed by Damien Keown

The Journal of Religion

Vol.77 No.2

April 1997

Pp.337-340

Copyright by University of Chicago


          Any addition to the meager literature on Buddhist ethics is welcome, 
            and the appearance of this volume from David Kalupahana suggests 
            that the subject is at last beginning to attract the attention it 
            deserves. It is encouraging to see scholars who have so far 
            concentrated on more traditional aspects of Buddhist philosophy turn 
            their attention to ethics, a comparatively new field where much 
            vital and challenging work remains to be done. It must be said at 
            the outset, however, that this slender volume does not mark a major 
            contribution to the discipline. The 146 pages of text are 
            distributed over seventeen short chapters, giving an average chapter 
            length of under nine pages. The initial suspicion that this is a 
            short book that spreads itself too thin is soon confirmed on 
            reading, particularly as there is a fair amount of material that is 
            of questionable relevance to ethics. 
            The volume is divided into three parts, entitled "Historical 
            Background and Problems," "The Moral Life, the Principle, and 
            Justification," and "Applications of the Principle." Part I begins 
            with a twenty-five-page discussion of pre-Buddhist moral theories. 
            Although this contains the headings "Deontology" and 
            "Utilitarianism," these terms are neither defined nor explained, and 
            the content is largely a summary of pre-Buddhist religious and 
            philosophical ideas of the kind that would be found in an 
            introduction to Indian religion. The need for such an introductory 
            survey is questionable in a book of this length, particularly since 
            no clear conclusions about Buddhist ethics are drawn from it. When 
            pre-Buddhist religious developments are characterized with ethical 
            terminology, furthermore, it is done in an offhand way, as if no 
            demonstration is required. For example, Arjuna's dilemma in the 
            Bhagavadgita is simplistically set up as illustrating the difference 
            between deontology and utilitarianism. Kalupahana writes: "Arjuna, 
            the hero of the Bhagavadgita, was reluctant to engage in battle 
            against his kith and kin, fearing that it would lead to unnecessary 
            death and destruction, thereby paving the way for the disintegration 
            of the family, social structure, and moral and religious values. He 
            therefore started as a utilitarian unwilling to cause pain and 
            suffering to human beings, not prepared to disrupt the social fabric 
            but willing to lay down even his own life in order to guarantee 
            'maximum happiness'" (p. 7). But since when did unwillingness to 
            cause pain and suffering make someone a utilitarian? The essence of 
            Arjuna's dilemma is surely that of a conflict between duties - his 
            duty as a ksatriya versus his duty to his relations and friends. His 
            initial decision not to fight - and to accept death as the price of 
            his decision - is not the result of a computation made according to 
            some hedonistic calculus but the simple recognition that he is 
            unable to do what his duty requires. 
            In the section on utilitarianism beginning on page 10, Kalupahana 
            again attempts to set up a contrast between deontology and 
            utilitarianism, regarding them as belonging to "two different 
            cultures" in India. He writes: "While the Bhagavadgita represents 
            the ultimate development of the deontology of the Brahmanical 
            tradition . . . utilitarianism was part of the tradition that came 
            to be identified as the ascetic, or sramana" (p. 10). This is an 
            extraordinary claim. Why should the sramana movement be thought 
            utilitarian? Because, according to the author, the movement 
            subscribed to the theory of the four stages of life (asramadharma), 
            and the duties required in the four stages of life could be 
            incompatible with caste duty (varnadharma). But what does this have 
            to do with utilitarianism? This is not explained, and the author 
            moves on to describe Kautilya as an early exponent of 
            utilitarianism, making further questionable claims such as that he 
            "established utilitarian thought on a moral foundation," that Mill 
            was his "Western counterpart," and that Mill and Kautilya "tried to 
            reconcile the [sic] deontology and utilitarianism" (p. 15). 
            Virtually no arguments are offered in support of these assertions. 
            Toward the end of this section there is a reference to the Buddha's 
            "moral pragmatism" (p. 16) without any clarification of what this 
            means. Since the Buddha was a sramana, should he not be classed as a 
            utilitarian rather than a pragmatist? What is the difference between 
            the two? Questions of this kind are left hanging in the air while 
            the discussion moves on to summarize the views of the five heretical 
            teachers, including a disproportionate five-page review of the 
            teachings of Jainism. It is hard to resist the impression that some 
            of this material has been pasted into a discussion of ethics rather 
            than written specifically for it. 
            Chapter 2, entitled "Knowledge," is a summary of Buddhist theories 
            of epistemology that has almost nothing to say about ethics till the 
            end. Chapter 3, "The Fact-Value Distinction," is notable for its 
            remarks about Aristotle, such as that "Aristotle's araetic [sic], or 
            virtue-based, ethics appears to be what eventually led to emotivism" 
            (p. 38). It is hard to think of a less likely source for emotivism 
            than Aristotle. The claim that Aristotle "shied away from 
            formulating any moral principles" also needs qualification - is the 
            Doctrine of the Mean not an example of one such moral principle? On 
            a positive note, the recognition that Buddhism does not aim at the 
            suppression of feeling but only the abandoning of "excessive desire 
            and lust (chandaraga)" is well made (p. 41). The two remaining 
            chapters contain little of note, and at the end of part 1 the 
            impression is of a superficial discussion around tangential themes 
            with few points of any substance having been made. 
            The forty-five pages that make up part 2 are concerned with 
            summarizing aspects of Buddhist ethics such as brahmacariya, the 
            virtues, and the Eightfold Path. This part is less confused than 
            part 1, but once again there are many statements calling for 
            clarification. For example, on page 80: "We have already observed 
            that virtues are the stepping-stones of the moral life and that they 
            are not valued for their own sake. The Buddha wanted to recognize 
            their usefulness and then proceed to explain something more useful, 
            namely the moral life." The claim that virtues are not part of the 
            moral life would strike most ethicists as strange. What Kalupahana 
            is suggesting is that the virtues (by which he seems to mean sila) 
            are the preliminary to the Eightfold Path. The latter forms a 
            "bridge between the life of virtues and ultimate freedom" (p. 81). 
            Kalupahana seems unaware that this means-end concept of morality in 
            Buddhism has been the subject of major critique in recent years by 
            several authors. Indeed, the book shows no awareness at all of 
            recent work in the field of Buddhist ethics and appears to have been 
            written in a vacuum. 
            Part 3 is the most interesting part of the book. Although only 
            thirty-three pages long, some useful points are made in the five 
            chapters dealing with society, economics, politics, law, and nature. 
            These chapters discuss important contemporary issues, and one wishes 
            they had been given a more central place. Although little of 
            substance is said, some interesting lines of argument are introduced 
            that could be developed in interesting ways. 
            Ethics in Early Buddhism is too slight to be an important 
            contribution to the study of Buddhist ethics. The attempt to 
            characterize Indian religions in terms of Western ethical categories 
            is not well handled. Labels are applied to movements and texts 
            without proper discussion, and terms like "deontology" and 
            "utilitarianism" are used with little consideration of how 
            appropriate they are. Kalupahana's notion of the Western philosophy 
            that has most in common with Buddhist ethics turns out to be 
            "Jamesean pragmatism," but we learn this in the glossary of all 
            places. The author also states there (p. 159) that the Buddha "could 
            not subscribe" to a moral absolute, defined as "a principle that is 
            universally binding, not only because it applies to all people at 
            all times under any circumstances, but also because it can never be 
            overridden by any other principle." But does not the First Precept 
            embody a principle of this kind? Perhaps the author thinks it does 
            not, but the complete absence of any discussion of the matter one 
            way or the other is a major defect, and typical of the book's 
            reluctance to engage with serious issues and alternative 
            perspectives.