The Journal of Religion
Vol.77 No.2
April 1997
Pp.337-340
Copyright by University of Chicago
Any addition to the meager literature on Buddhist ethics is welcome, and the appearance of this volume from David Kalupahana suggests that the subject is at last beginning to attract the attention it deserves. It is encouraging to see scholars who have so far concentrated on more traditional aspects of Buddhist philosophy turn their attention to ethics, a comparatively new field where much vital and challenging work remains to be done. It must be said at the outset, however, that this slender volume does not mark a major contribution to the discipline. The 146 pages of text are distributed over seventeen short chapters, giving an average chapter length of under nine pages. The initial suspicion that this is a short book that spreads itself too thin is soon confirmed on reading, particularly as there is a fair amount of material that is of questionable relevance to ethics. The volume is divided into three parts, entitled "Historical Background and Problems," "The Moral Life, the Principle, and Justification," and "Applications of the Principle." Part I begins with a twenty-five-page discussion of pre-Buddhist moral theories. Although this contains the headings "Deontology" and "Utilitarianism," these terms are neither defined nor explained, and the content is largely a summary of pre-Buddhist religious and philosophical ideas of the kind that would be found in an introduction to Indian religion. The need for such an introductory survey is questionable in a book of this length, particularly since no clear conclusions about Buddhist ethics are drawn from it. When pre-Buddhist religious developments are characterized with ethical terminology, furthermore, it is done in an offhand way, as if no demonstration is required. For example, Arjuna's dilemma in the Bhagavadgita is simplistically set up as illustrating the difference between deontology and utilitarianism. Kalupahana writes: "Arjuna, the hero of the Bhagavadgita, was reluctant to engage in battle against his kith and kin, fearing that it would lead to unnecessary death and destruction, thereby paving the way for the disintegration of the family, social structure, and moral and religious values. He therefore started as a utilitarian unwilling to cause pain and suffering to human beings, not prepared to disrupt the social fabric but willing to lay down even his own life in order to guarantee 'maximum happiness'" (p. 7). But since when did unwillingness to cause pain and suffering make someone a utilitarian? The essence of Arjuna's dilemma is surely that of a conflict between duties - his duty as a ksatriya versus his duty to his relations and friends. His initial decision not to fight - and to accept death as the price of his decision - is not the result of a computation made according to some hedonistic calculus but the simple recognition that he is unable to do what his duty requires. In the section on utilitarianism beginning on page 10, Kalupahana again attempts to set up a contrast between deontology and utilitarianism, regarding them as belonging to "two different cultures" in India. He writes: "While the Bhagavadgita represents the ultimate development of the deontology of the Brahmanical tradition . . . utilitarianism was part of the tradition that came to be identified as the ascetic, or sramana" (p. 10). This is an extraordinary claim. Why should the sramana movement be thought utilitarian? Because, according to the author, the movement subscribed to the theory of the four stages of life (asramadharma), and the duties required in the four stages of life could be incompatible with caste duty (varnadharma). But what does this have to do with utilitarianism? This is not explained, and the author moves on to describe Kautilya as an early exponent of utilitarianism, making further questionable claims such as that he "established utilitarian thought on a moral foundation," that Mill was his "Western counterpart," and that Mill and Kautilya "tried to reconcile the [sic] deontology and utilitarianism" (p. 15). Virtually no arguments are offered in support of these assertions. Toward the end of this section there is a reference to the Buddha's "moral pragmatism" (p. 16) without any clarification of what this means. Since the Buddha was a sramana, should he not be classed as a utilitarian rather than a pragmatist? What is the difference between the two? Questions of this kind are left hanging in the air while the discussion moves on to summarize the views of the five heretical teachers, including a disproportionate five-page review of the teachings of Jainism. It is hard to resist the impression that some of this material has been pasted into a discussion of ethics rather than written specifically for it. Chapter 2, entitled "Knowledge," is a summary of Buddhist theories of epistemology that has almost nothing to say about ethics till the end. Chapter 3, "The Fact-Value Distinction," is notable for its remarks about Aristotle, such as that "Aristotle's araetic [sic], or virtue-based, ethics appears to be what eventually led to emotivism" (p. 38). It is hard to think of a less likely source for emotivism than Aristotle. The claim that Aristotle "shied away from formulating any moral principles" also needs qualification - is the Doctrine of the Mean not an example of one such moral principle? On a positive note, the recognition that Buddhism does not aim at the suppression of feeling but only the abandoning of "excessive desire and lust (chandaraga)" is well made (p. 41). The two remaining chapters contain little of note, and at the end of part 1 the impression is of a superficial discussion around tangential themes with few points of any substance having been made. The forty-five pages that make up part 2 are concerned with summarizing aspects of Buddhist ethics such as brahmacariya, the virtues, and the Eightfold Path. This part is less confused than part 1, but once again there are many statements calling for clarification. For example, on page 80: "We have already observed that virtues are the stepping-stones of the moral life and that they are not valued for their own sake. The Buddha wanted to recognize their usefulness and then proceed to explain something more useful, namely the moral life." The claim that virtues are not part of the moral life would strike most ethicists as strange. What Kalupahana is suggesting is that the virtues (by which he seems to mean sila) are the preliminary to the Eightfold Path. The latter forms a "bridge between the life of virtues and ultimate freedom" (p. 81). Kalupahana seems unaware that this means-end concept of morality in Buddhism has been the subject of major critique in recent years by several authors. Indeed, the book shows no awareness at all of recent work in the field of Buddhist ethics and appears to have been written in a vacuum. Part 3 is the most interesting part of the book. Although only thirty-three pages long, some useful points are made in the five chapters dealing with society, economics, politics, law, and nature. These chapters discuss important contemporary issues, and one wishes they had been given a more central place. Although little of substance is said, some interesting lines of argument are introduced that could be developed in interesting ways. Ethics in Early Buddhism is too slight to be an important contribution to the study of Buddhist ethics. The attempt to characterize Indian religions in terms of Western ethical categories is not well handled. Labels are applied to movements and texts without proper discussion, and terms like "deontology" and "utilitarianism" are used with little consideration of how appropriate they are. Kalupahana's notion of the Western philosophy that has most in common with Buddhist ethics turns out to be "Jamesean pragmatism," but we learn this in the glossary of all places. The author also states there (p. 159) that the Buddha "could not subscribe" to a moral absolute, defined as "a principle that is universally binding, not only because it applies to all people at all times under any circumstances, but also because it can never be overridden by any other principle." But does not the First Precept embody a principle of this kind? Perhaps the author thinks it does not, but the complete absence of any discussion of the matter one way or the other is a major defect, and typical of the book's reluctance to engage with serious issues and alternative perspectives.