Vasubandhu's 'Treatise on the Three Natures' translated from

the Tibetan edition with a commentary

by Garfield, Jay L.

Asian Philosophy

Vol.6 No.2

July 1997

Pp.133-154

COPYRIGHT 1997 Journals Oxford Ltd. (UK)


            1. Introduction 
            The present text Trisvabhavanirdesac (Rang bzhin gsum nges par bstan 
            pa) is one 
            of Vasubandhu's short treatises (the others being the Treatise in 
            Twenty Stanzas 
            [Vimsatika] and the Treatise in Thirty Stanzas [Trimsatika]) 
            expounding his 
            cittamatra, 
            or mind-only philosophy. Vasubandhu and his older brother Asanga are 
            regarded 
            as the 
            Fourth or Fifth century CE as the major philosophical rival within 
            the Mahayana 
            Buddhist tradition to the older Madhyamaka tradition. The latter 
            school, 
            founded by 
            Nagarjuna, urges the emptiness -- the lack of essence or 
            substantial, 
            independent 
            reality -- of all things, including both external phenomena and 
            mind.(2) 
            Vasubandhu, 
            however, reinterprets the emptiness of the object as being its lack 
            of external 
            reality, and 
            its purely mind-dependent, or ideal status.(3) At the same time, 
            however, he 
            argues that the foundational mind is non-empty since it truly exists 
            as the 
            substratum of the 
            apparent reality represented in our experience. The position is 
            hence akin to 
            the idealisms defended by such Western philosophers as Berkeley, 
            Kant and 
            Schopenhauer.(4) 
            While Trisvabhavanirdesa is arguably the most philosophically 
            detailed and 
            comprehensive of the three short works on this topic composed by 
            Vasubandhu, as 
            well as 
            the clearest, it is almost never read or taught in contemporary 
            traditional 
            Buddhist 
            cultures or centres of learning. The reason for this is simple: this 
            is the 
            only one of 
            Vasubandhu's root texts for which no auto-commentary exists.(5) For 
            this 
            reason, 
            none of Vasubandhu's students composed commentaries on the text and 
            there is 
            hence 
            no recognized lineage of transmission for the text. So nobody within 
            the 
            Tibetan 
            tradition (the only extant Mahayana monastic scholarly tradition) 
            could 
            consider 
            him/herself authorized to teach the text. So it is simply not 
            studied. This is 
            a great pity. 
            It is a beautiful and deep philosophical essay and an unparalleled 
            introduction 
            to the 
            cittamatra system. 
            The text introduces the fundamental doctrine of Buddhist idealism, 
            and 
            clarifies in 
            remarkably short compass its relations to the other principal 
            doctrines of that 
            school -- that all external appearances are merely ideal and 
            originate from 
            potentials for 
            experience carried in the mind. The central topic of the text is the 
            exposition 
            of how this view 
            entails the cittamatra theory of the three natures -- the view that 
            every 
            object of 
            experience is characterized by three distinct but interdependent 
            natures. 
            Vasubandhu's 
            idealism is distinctive in its insistence that a coherent idealism 
            requires the 
            positing of 
            these three natures, and in its subtle analysis of the complex 
            relations 
            between the 
            natures themselves, involving the thesis of their surface diversity 
            but deep 
            unity.(6) 
            This text also presents a creative union of ontology and 
            phenomenology. 
            Vasubandhu's characterization of the status of the objects of 
            experience is at 
            the same 
            time self-consciously a characterization of the character of 
            subjectivity 
            itself. Not only 
            will Vasubandhu argue that we can only make sense of objects if we 
            ascribe to 
            them 
            these three triune natures, but he will argue that a complete 
            account of 
            experience -- especially of the experience of a sophisticated and 
            accomplished 
            philosopher or 
            meditator -- requires an account of three distinct kinds of 
            subjectivity, which 
            are related to 
            one another as are the three natures themselves. This phenomenology 
            is crucial 
            to the 
            soteriological purport of the system. For this is not speculative 
            philosophy 
            for its own 
            sake, but a philosophical system designed to guide a practitioner to 
            buddhahood 
            in order that s/he can work to alleviate the suffering of all 
            sentient beings. 
            Trisvabhavanirdesa is unique in its exposition of idealism as 
            involving the 
            doctrine of 
            the three natures, in its detailed analysis of the natures 
            themselves and in 
            its exploration 
            of their relations to one another. In Vimsatika-karika Vasubandhu 
            clearly 
            defends 
            idealism against a series of objections, but does not explicitly 
            articulate the 
            roles of the 
            three natures in his idealistic theory or expound its structure. In 
            Trimsika-karika 
            Vasubandhu explores the relation between the three natures and the 
            three 
            naturelessnesses (naturelessness with respect to characteristic 
            [laksana-nihsvabhavata, mtshan 
            nyid ngo bo nyid med], naturelessness with respect to production 
            [utpatti-nihsvabhavata, 
            skye ba ngo bo niyd med] and ultimate naturelessness 
            [paramartha-nihsvabhavata, 
            don dam pa'i ngo bo nyid med]) adumbrated in the 
            Samdhinirmocana-sutra, but does 
            not explore their relation to idealism, per se, or their relations 
            to one 
            another. It is only in 
            the present text that he explicitly analyses idealism as implicating 
            the three 
            natures, and 
            explains in detail how they are interconnected. 
            Sthiramati, in his commentary on Trimsika-karika, argues that the 
            three 
            natures and three naturelessnesses are equivalent. His understanding 
            of the 
            three natures 
            as equivalent to the three naturelessnessess of the 
            Samdhinirmocana-sutra is 
            adopted 
            uncritically by such Tibetan doxographers as Tsong Khapa(7) and 
            mKhas grub.(8) 
            The adoption of this commentarial tradition, which emphasises the 
            homogeneity 
            of the Samdhinirmocana-sutra with Vasubandhu's and Asanga's thought, 
            along with 
            the exposition of the three natures as presented in Trimsatika and 
            Vimsatika 
            reinforces the 
            elision of this more mature and explicit articulation of 
            Vasubandhu's theory 
            from subsequent developments of Yogacara. The emphasis of the 
            dominant 
            Madhyamaka school on naturelessness as a fundamental metaphysical 
            tenet, and 
            its need to see Yogacara as the penultimate step to its own 
            standpoint lends 
            further impetus to this tendency to assimilate these two doctrines. 
            Of all of 
            the Madhyamika, only Candrakirti 
            really takes the trisvabhava doctrine itself seriously as a target 
            for critique 
            (dBu ma la jugs pa/Madhyamakavatara).(10) 
            The thirty-eight verses of the text divide neatly into six sections. 
            In the 
            first six verses 
            Vasubandhu introduces the three natures and provides a preliminary 
            characterization 
            of each. In verses 7-9 he sketches two schemata for thinking about 
            the 
            character of 
            mind from the standpoint of three nature theory. Verses 10-21 
            develop a 
            dialectically 
            complex and elegant discussion of how to view the polar pairs of 
            existence/non-existence, duality/unity and affliction/non-affliction 
            in 
            relation to each of the three 
            natures, culminating in a discussion of the senses in which the 
            natures are 
            identical to 
            one another and the senses in which they are different. Verses 22-25 
            present 
            the natures hierarchically from the standpoint of pedagogy and 
            soteriology. 
            Vasubandhu 
            presents the famous simile of the hallucinatory elephant conjured by 
            the stage 
            magician 
            in verses 26-34. This is probably the most famous and oft-cited 
            moment in this 
            text. 
            In a vivid and simple image Vasubandhu presents a way of 
            understanding the 
            three 
            natures, their relation to one another, to idealism, and of the 
            phenomenology 
            they 
            suggest to Buddhist soteriology. The concluding four verses are 
            devoted to the 
            soteriological implications of the text. 
            Trisvabhavanirdesa is not only a philosophically subtle text. It is 
            also a 
            considerable 
            literary and poetic achievement. (Much of the elegance of 
            Vasubandhu's 
            Sanskrit is preserved in the Tibetan translation. I have found it 
            difficult 
            to produce a translation 
            that does proper justice to the poetic value of the text while 
            remaining 
            faithful to the 
            philosophical ideas and rhetorical structure.) The doctrine it 
            expounds is 
            packed with 
            dynamic tension born of constantly impending paradox and of the need 
            
            continuously 
            to balance several levels of discourse. The poetic text that 
            develops this 
            doctrine mirrors 
            that tension in its constant shifting of level; in its frequent 
            double entendre 
            allowing 
            claims to be made at two or more levels simultaneously; and in its 
            multi-leveled 
            discourse in which claims that appear contradictory are reconcile, 
            albeit 
            often in startling and revealing ways. The poem is full of 
            unexpected 
            rhetorical and philosophical turns, and is structured so as to 
            reflect the 
            ontological and phenomenological 
            theory it articulates. The language is as spare and vibrant as the 
            radiant 
            mind-only 
            ontology it presents. 
            2. The Text of Trisvabhavanirdesa(11) 
            1. The imagined, the other-dependent and 
            The consummate. 
            These are the three natures 
            Which should be deeply understood. 
            2. Arising through dependence on conditions and 
            Existing through being imagined, 
            It is therefore called other-dependent 
            And is said to be merely imaginary. 
            3. The external non-existence 
            Of what appears in the way it appears, 
            Since it is never otherwise, 
            Is known as the nature of the consummate. 
            4. If anything appears, it is imagined. 
            The way it appears is as duality. 
            What is the consequence of its non-existence? 
            The fact of non-duality! 
            5. What is the imagination of the non-existent? 
            Since what is imagined absolutely never 
            Exists in the way it is imagined, 
            It is mind that constructs that illusion. 
            6. Because it is a cause and an effect, 
            The mind has two aspects. 
            As the foundation consciousness it creates thought; 
            Known as the emerged consciousness it has seven aspects. 
            7. The first, because it collects the seeds 
            Of suffering is called `mind'. 
            The second, because of the constant emergence 
            Of the various aspects of things is so called. 
            8. One should think of the illusory non-existent 
            As threefold: 
            Completely ripened, grasped as other, 
            And as appearance. 
            9. The first, because it itself ripens, 
            Is the root consciousness. 
            The others are emergent consciousness, 
            Having emerged from the conceptualization of seer and seen. 
            10. Existence and non-existence, duality and unity; 
            Freedom from affliction and afflicted; 
            Through characteristics, and through distinctions, 
            These natures are known to be profound. 
            11. Since it appears as existent 
            Though it is non-existent, 
            The imagined nature 
            Is said to have the characteristics of existence and non-existence. 
            12. Since it exists as an illusory entity 
            And is non-existent in the way it appears 
            The other-dependent nature 
            Is said to have the characteristics of existence and non-existence. 
            13. Since it is the non-existence of duality 
            And exists as non-duality 
            The consummate nature 
            Is said to have the characteristics of existence and non-existence. 
            14. Moreover, since as imagined there are two aspects, 
            But existence and non-existence are unitary, 
            The nature imagined by the ignorant 
            Is said to be both dual and unitary. 
            15. Since as an object of thought it is dual, 
            But as a mere appearance it is unitary, 
            The other-dependent nature 
            Is said to be both dual and unitary. 
            16. Since it is the essence of dual entities 
            And is a unitary non-duality, 
            The consummate nature 
            Is said to be both dual and unitary. 
            17. The imagined and the other-dependent 
            Are said to be characterized by misery (due to ignorant craving). 
            The consummate is free of 
            The characteristic of desire. 
            18. Since the former has the nature of a false duality 
            And the latter is the non-existence of that nature, 
            The imagined and the consummate 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            19. Since the former has the nature of non-duality, 
            And the latter has the nature of non-existent duality, 
            The consummate and the imagined 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            20. Since the former is deceptive in the way it appears, 
            And the latter has the nature of its not being that way, 
            The other-dependent and the consummate 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            21. Since the former has the nature of a non-existent duality, 
            And the latter is its non-existence in the way it appears, 
            The other-dependent and the consummate 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            22. But conventionally, 
            The natures are explained in order and 
            Based on that one enters them 
            In a particular order, it is said. 
            23. The imagined is entirely conventional. 
            The other-dependent is attached to convention. 
            The consummate, cutting convention, 
            Is said to be of a different nature. 
            24. Having first entered into the non-existence of duality 
            Which is the dependent, one understands 
            The non-existent duality 
            Which is the imagined. 
            25. Then one enters the consummate. 
            Its nature is the non-existence of duality. 
            Therefore it is explained 
            To be both existent and non-existent. 
            26. These three natures 
            Have the characteristics of being non-cognizable and non-dual. 
            One is completely non-existent; the second is therefore 
            non-existent. 
            The third has the nature of that non-existence. 
            27. Like an elephant that appears 
            Through the power of a magician's mantra -- 
            Only the percept appears, 
            The elephant is completely non-existent. 
            28. The imagined nature is the elephant; 
            The other-dependent nature is the visual percept; 
            The non-existence of the elephant therein 
            Is explained to be the consummate. 
            29. Through the root consciousness 
            The nonexistent duality appears. 
            But since the duality is completely non-existent, 
            There is only a percept. 
            30. The root consciousness is like the mantra. 
            Reality can be compared to the wood. 
            Imagination is like the perception of the elephant. 
            Duality can be seen as the elephant. 
            31. When one understands how things are, 
            Perfect knowledge, abandonment, 
            And accomplishment -- 
            These three characteristics are simultaneously achieved. 
            32. Knowledge is non-perception; 
            Abandonment is non-appearance; 
            Attainment is accomplished through non-dual perception. 
            That is direct manifestation. 
            33. Through the non-perception of the elephant, 
            The vanishing of its percept occurs; 
            And so does the perception of the piece of wood. 
            This is how it is in the magic show. 
            34. In the same way through the non-perception of duality 
            There is the vanishing of duality. 
            When it vanishes completely, 
            Non-dual awareness arises. 
            35. Through perceiving correctly, 
            Through seeing the non-referentiality of mental states, 
            Through following the three wisdoms, 
            One will effortlessly attain liberation. 
            36. Through the perception of mind-only 
            One achieves the non-perception of objects; 
            Through the non-perception of objects 
            There is also the non-perception of mind. 
            37. Through the non-duality of perception, 
            Arises the perception of the fundamental nature of reality. 
            Through the perception of the fundamental nature of reality 
            Arises the perception of the radiant. 
            38. Through the perception of the radiant, 
            And through achieving the three supreme Buddha-bodies, 
            And through possessing bodhi: 
            Having achieved this, the sage will benefit him/herself and others. 
            3. The Text With Commentary 
            1. The imagined, the other-dependent and 
            The consummate. 
            These are the three natures. 
            Which should be deeply understood. 
            Every phenomenon, according to cittamatra metaphysics has all three 
            of these 
            natures -- three ways of being. It is not the case that some have 
            one nature 
            and some have 
            others; nor that phenomena appear to have one or another of the 
            three, but in 
            fact have 
            another. The three are necessarily copresent in every phenomenon, 
            and are, 
            though 
            distinct, mutually implicative. 
            Let us pause for a moment over the three terms themselves, whose 
            translation into 
            English is no straightforward matter. Each is a nature (Tib: rang 
            bzhin, Skt: 
            svabhava). So each is part of what it is to be a thing -- not an 
            accidental 
            attribute that a 
            thing might have. But each of the three qualifiers added to this 
            term to 
            denote one 
            of the three natures creates a subtly ambiguous compound, and plays 
            on this 
            ambiguity form part of the structure of Vasubandhu's ingenious verse 
            treatise. 
            On the 
            one hand, each characterizes the nature itself -- part of what it is 
            to be a 
            phenomenon. 
            On the other hand, each characterizes the relation of the subject to 
            the 
            phenomenon, 
            or the character of the subjectivity that constitutes the 
            representation of the 
            phenomenon. This duality is not surprising, for this is an 
            idealistic 
            treatise. As far as 
            Vasubandhu is concerned, what it is to be a phenomenon is to be an 
            object of a 
            mind, 
            and this treatise is an exploration of what it is to be an object so 
            
            conceived. So 
            questions about subjectivity and questions concerning the ontology 
            of the 
            object are 
            closely intertwined. 
            "Imagined" translates the Tibetan brtags or Sanskrit parikalpita. 
            The terms 
            connote 
            construction by the mind, more than they do non-existence -- more 
            akin to 
            hallucination than fiction. But this simile can be misleading. To be 
            imagined 
            in this senses is not 
            to be hallucinatory as opposed to being real -- it is to be 
            constructed as the 
            object that 
            it is by the operation of the mind. "Other-dependent" translates 
            gzhan gyi 
            dbang or 
            paratantra. Something that is other-dependent in this sense exists 
            only in and 
            through 
            dependence on another thing. In this case, the emphasis will be that 
            phenomena 
            exist 
            in dependence upon the mind and its process.(12) 
            I use "consummate" to translate yongs su grub pa or parinispanna. 
            This is 
            the most 
            difficult of these three terms to translate. Others have used 
            "perfect", 
            "perfected", 
            "thoroughly established", "thoroughly existent", "completed" and 
            "ultimate".(13) 
            Each of these choices has merit, and the variety of options 
            illustrates the 
            range of 
            associations the term has in Tibetan or Sanskrit. When affixed to 
            "nature" it 
            connotes 
            on the objective side the nature an object has when it is thoroughly 
            
            understood. On the 
            subjective side, it connotes the nature apparent to one who is fully 
            
            accomplished 
            intellectually and meditatively. It represents the highest and most 
            complete 
            understanding of a phenomenon. It is important, however, not to 
            misinterpret 
            this term to connote 
            the real nature as opposed to the unreal natures denoted by the 
            terms 
            "imaginary" and 
            "other-dependent", or the ultimate, as opposed to the conventional 
            nature of 
            things. 
            Ultimately, all phenomena have all three natures. Each is real; each 
            must be 
            understood 
            in order to understand the nature of things; each subjective 
            relation to 
            things is present 
            in a full understanding of a phenomenon.(14) 
            2. Arising through dependence on conditions and 
            Existing through being imagined, 
            It is therefore called other-dependent 
            And is said to be merely imaginary. 
            Vasubandhu begins by sketching in the second and third verses the 
            outlines of 
            the 
            relation between the three natures. In the second verse he focuses 
            on the 
            relation 
            between the first two. Any phenomenon comes into existence in 
            dependence upon 
            various causes and conditions. But Vasubandhu here calls attention 
            to a special 
            dimension of this dependence. For anything to exist as an object, 
            its objective 
            existence 
            is dependent upon mental causes and conditions. This is a 
            straightforwardly 
            Kantian 
            point -- that there are conditions on the side of the subject that 
            make it 
            possible for 
            anything to exist as an object. 
            But whatever is so dependent, and hence, when seen from this 
            standpoint, the 
            content of a mental act, is nonetheless represented as an 
            independent existent. 
            Let us 
            consider for example my perceptual representation of the screen on 
            which these 
            words appear as I type. I see it not as my representation, but 
            rather as 
            something that 
            exists independent of, external to, and standing against my mind and 
            perceptual 
            faculties. No matter how thoroughgoing an idealist I may be in my 
            philosophical 
            moods, ordinary perception delivers me not imaginary objects seen as 
            imaginary, 
            but 
            rather objects seen as external. But they do not, from this 
            philosophical 
            standpoint, 
            exist in that way. In fact they are merely dependent on and, 
            transcendentally, 
            internal 
            to, my mind. For this reason we can say that the content of my 
            mental acts, 
            seen as 
            content, is other-dependent, in virtue of its dependence on my mind, 
            but seen 
            as it is 
            experienced, it is imaginary, since considered in the way it appears 
            to exist, 
            it is in fact 
            non-existent. 
            3. The external non-existence 
            Of what appears in the way it appears, 
            Since it is never otherwise, 
            Is know as the nature of the consummate. 
            The third verse emphasizes this last point and uses it to connect 
            these first 
            two 
            natures to the consummate nature: things appear to us as 
            independently 
            existent. 
            They do so in virtue of their dependence upon other such things and 
            upon our 
            minds 
            (which -- in an important sense to be discussed later -- do share 
            these three 
            natures). 
            But the fact is that given their actual mind-dependent status, of 
            which we can 
            be aware through careful philosophical reflection or through 
            extensive 
            meditative accomplishment, we can say that these apparent 
            things -- independently existent computers, camels and coffee cups 
            -- are always 
            non-existent. What exists in their place 
            are states of mind masquerading as independent phenomena. That 
            non-existence -- the non existence of the apparent reality -- is the 
            consummate 
            nature that all 
            phenomena have. 
            The next two verses examine two consequences of this negative 
            characterisation of 
            the consummate nature: the co-existence of subject-object duality in 
            the first 
            two natures with non-duality in the consummate, and the 
            mind-dependence of the 
            imagined nature: 
            4. If anything appears, it is imagined. 
            The way it appears is as duality. 
            What is the consequence of its non-existence? 
            The fact of non-duality! 
            Whatever appears to us as an object, we have seen, does so in its 
            imagined 
            nature. In 
            any such appearance, the fact that the object is presented to us as 
            independent 
            entails 
            the fact that it is presented as wholly other than the mind that 
            apprehends it. 
            This is 
            the point that Kant makes against Berkeley when he urges in the 
            Refutation of 
            Idealism 
            that even though in a transcendental sense all appearances are in 
            us, in an 
            empirical 
            sense, for anything to appear to us in space, it appears to us as 
            outside 
            us.(15) 
            Schopenhauer hones this point and wields it against Kant himself 
            when he points 
            out 
            that any account of the genesis of representation that harmonizes 
            with a 
            coherent 
            transcendental idealist account of the ontology of representation 
            must grant 
            phenomena a genuine independent empirical reality in order to 
            account for their 
            causal 
            impact upon us that is responsible for our cognitive apprehension of 
            them.(16) 
            But, 
            he argues, such an idealism must also grant them a status as mere 
            representations 
            when we consider them as they appear to us. Interestingly, this 
            point is made 
            on the 
            way to an account of a third nature of which Schopenhauer(17) 
            charges Kant of 
            being unaware -- their status as noumena, or will, in which all 
            subject-object 
            duality 
            disappears.(18) 
            5. What is the imagination of the non-existent? 
            Since what is imagined absolutely never 
            Exists in the way it is imagined, 
            It is mind that constructs that illusion. 
            Vasubandhu here simply repeats the tight connection between the 
            account 
            offered of 
            the status of phenomena as imagined and their mind-dependence. Since 
            the 
            imagined 
            nature is in fact totally imaginary, it does not arise from the side 
            of the 
            thing which 
            appears. Rather it is an artifact of the operation of the mind. 
            The next four verses sketch two alternative ways of presenting the 
            nature of 
            mind in 
            Vasubandhu's idealistic system. In verses 6 and 7 he presents a 
            division that 
            distinguishes the mind in its role as subject from the mind in its 
            role as 
            object: 
            6. Because it is a cause and an effect, 
            The mind has two aspects. 
            As the foundation consciousness it creates thought; 
            Known as the emerged consciousness it has seven aspects. 
            Vasubandhu, in another move prescient of Kant,(19) distinguishes the 
            mind in 
            its role 
            as transcendental subject from its role as object, as it appears to 
            itself. In 
            the first aspect, 
            to which Vasubandhu refers as the "foundation consciousness", (Tib: 
            kun gzhi, 
            Skt: 
            alaya-vijnana) the mind functions as the condition of the appearance 
            of 
            phenomena, 
            and hence as the ground of the possibility of the imagined and 
            other-dependent 
            natures. But in its second aspect -- the "emerged consciousness" 
            (Tib: `jug pa, 
            Skt: 
            pavrttivijnana) -- the mind exists as the object of introspection, 
            and is 
            conditioned both 
            by external phenomena that appear in perception and by its own 
            phenomena. Hence 
            it 
            constantly evolves, and emerges in new states as a consequence of 
            experience. 
            The 
            "seven aspects" to which Vasubandhu alludes are the five sensory 
            consciousnesses, the 
            introspective consciousness apprehending the self as object, and the 
            reflective 
            consciousness of the transcendental subject of experience. These 
            aspects are 
            hence 
            distinguished by their proper objects or spheres of operation. 
            7. The first, because it collects the seeds 
            Of suffering is called "mind". 
            The second, because of the constant emergence 
            Of the various aspects of things is so called. 
            Vasubandhu is making a tendentious etymological claim about the 
            Sanskrit term 
            translated here as "mind", citta. On one etymology, he claims, the 
            term is 
            derived from 
            cita, which means piled up or accumulated. Hence, he argues, "mind" 
            can be 
            thought of 
            as indicating a storehouse of seeds of experience or mental 
            potentials. In this 
            sense the 
            mind can be thought of as the location of the seeds of future 
            experiences. The 
            second 
            etymology, Vasubandhu contends, connects citta to the Sanskrit term 
            citra 
            meaning 
            various or manifold. This suggests the role of mind as a constantly 
            emerging 
            developing 
            phenomenon. Hence, Vasubandhu suggests, the very etymology of the 
            term connotes 
            its two parallel roles.(20) 
            The next two verses develop a three-fold account of the aspectual 
            character 
            of mind. 
            These are not intended as competitors to one another, but rather as 
            alternate, 
            compossible, ways to understand the multiple roles played by mind in 
            
            experience. 
            8. One should think of the illusory non-existent 
            As threefold: 
            Completely ripened, grasped as other, 
            And as appearance. 
            Here Vasubandhu notes three prima facie characteristics of the mind 
            in our 
            experience, 
            all on the side of its role as object of inner sense. First, insofar 
            as mind is 
            an object, and 
            hence an empirical phenomenon, it is a ripened potential -- the 
            fruit of a seed 
            of experience heretofore dormant in the foundation consciousness. 
            Secondly, and 
            perhaps 
            most paradoxically, since it appears as an object, it appears as 
            other than the 
            self to 
            which it appears. Here Vasubandhu is calling attention to the fact 
            that even in 
            apperception there is a duality between subject and object; a self 
            that appears 
            to us 
            appears as distinct from the ego to which it appears. Finally, the 
            self is an 
            appearance -- not a continuing, stable or independent phenomenon, 
            but rather as 
            a series of moments 
            of awareness, each an evanescent ripening of a potential for 
            consciousness, and 
            so like 
            all external objects, its apparent unity is a matter of 
            construction, not of 
            discovery in 
            some independently given noumenon.(21) 
            9. The first, because it itself ripens, 
            Is the root consciousness. 
            The others are emergent consciousness, 
            Having emerged from the conceptualization of seer and seen. 
            Nonetheless, Vasubandhu argues, the first of these three aspects has 
            a 
            particular 
            connection to the subject side of the self, as per the first 
            division, while 
            the second and 
            third aspects of this threefold division are better aligned with the 
            second 
            side of the first 
            division. The root (Tib: rtsa ba, Skt: mula), consciousness (the 
            same as the 
            foundation 
            consciousness) is not only the subject of all experience, it is also 
            the 
            repository of all of 
            the latencies, or potentials -- more often called the "seeds" -- 
            which, when 
            actualized, or 
            "ripened" become actual phenomena -- objects of experience. On the 
            other hand, 
            when 
            the self is represented as an object of experience in introspection, 
            it stands 
            over and 
            against the root consciousness of which it is an object. It is hence 
            in this 
            sense emergent 
            from the root consciousness and is "grasped as other than the self". 
            Finally in 
            being so 
            grasped, it is grasped as a series of evanescent moments of 
            experience. These 
            latter two 
            aspects hence emerge as aspects of the self considered as object; 
            the first as 
            an aspect 
            of self considered as subject, or as storehouse of latencies. 
            The next eleven verses develop a delicate and logically acrobatic 
            dialectic 
            concerning 
            the interplay of three pairs of contradictories and their relation 
            to the three 
            natures: 
            existence and non-existence; duality and unity; freedom from 
            afflictions and 
            affliction. 
            Vasubandhu will argue that each of the three natures is 
            characterised by both 
            members 
            of each of these contraries. He then argues that these natures are 
            each both 
            identical to 
            and distinct from one another. While it might be tempting and facile 
            to think 
            that here 
            Vasubandhu is simply trading in paradox or irony this would be a 
            mistake. This 
            important section of the treatise is centrally concerned with the 
            alternation 
            in voices 
            and perspectives represented by the three natures. They have a 
            phenomenological 
            side 
            to them, representing not only the tripartite ontological dimension 
            Vasubandhu sees in 
            all phenomena, but also the three phenomenological perspectives that 
            together 
            constitute the complex subjectivity Vasubandhu envisions. 
            10. Existence and non-existence, duality and unity; 
            Freedom from affliction and afflicted; 
            Through characteristics, and through distinctions, 
            These natures are known to be profound. 
            "Existence" and "non-existence" are understood here in a perfectly 
            ordinary 
            sense, 
            though of course a sense ordinary within the framework of idealism 
            generally. 
            Given 
            this context, of course, it will always be possible to ask about the 
            standpoint 
            from which 
            an assertion regarding existence is made. Is it from the standpoint 
            of 
            subjectivity -- that 
            is, an empirical, objective claim? Or is it from a transcendental 
            standpoint? 
            Moreover, 
            we can always ask whether when a thing is asserted to exist we mean 
            that it 
            exists in the 
            way in which it is apprehended, or whether it exists simpliciter. 
            So, for 
            instance, if I ask 
            whether the "water" I see on a hot highway on a December day exists, 
            one must 
            be careful: the mirage exists, no water does. The percept to which I 
            refer as 
            "water" exists, 
            but not in the manner in which it is apprehended. (And, of course, 
            if I am an 
            idealist, 
            from a transcendental perspective neither the water nor the mirage 
            can be said 
            to exist at all. Both are merely appearances.) 
            The duality/unity pair concerns subject/object duality. To assert 
            that 
            there is, from a 
            specific standpoint, a duality in this sense is to assert that from 
            that 
            standpoint there is 
            a real distinction between subject and object. To assert a unity or 
            a 
            non-duality is to 
            deny such a duality. The important thing to bear in mind regarding 
            this pair 
            as one 
            approaches Vasubandhu is that questions about duality and 
            non-duality can 
            always be 
            posed in both a metaphysical and a phenomenological voice. So, we 
            can ask of 
            each of 
            the natures in what sense it implicates such a duality as part of 
            the structure 
            of the 
            object of experience. But we can also ask the question regarding the 
            nature of 
            the 
            corresponding aspect of subjectivity itself. So in each case we can 
            ask 
            whether, or in 
            what sense, in a subject considering things as other-dependent, etc. 
            there is 
            such a duality, 
            as well as asking whether, or in what sense, each nature implicates 
            such a 
            duality in the 
            structure of the object. 
            The third pair -- affliction/freedom from affliction -- introduces 
            specifically Buddhist 
            soteriological concerns. Again, the concerns in play are both 
            ontological and 
            phenomenological. The afflictions are those associated with the 
            suffering of 
            samsara or 
            cyclic existence. Those include not only physical and psychological 
            suffering 
            themselves 
            but also the craving and grasping which are their proximal causes 
            and, most 
            importantly in this context, the primal ignorance regarding the 
            nature of 
            things that takes the 
            phenomena of experience and the self to be inherently, or 
            substantially 
            existent, as 
            opposed to being empty of substance. So we can say either that a 
            mind 
            apprehending 
            an object is afflicted in virtue of regarding that object as 
            inherently 
            existent or that the 
            object as perceived is an afflicted object. In the latter case we 
            are saying 
            that the object 
            itself in virtue of one or more of its natures is constituted in a 
            manner 
            essentially 
            implicating the afflictions. (22) Vasubandhu begins by arguing that 
            the 
            imagined nature 
            involves both existence and non-existence. 
            11. Since it appears as existent 
            Though it is non-existent, 
            The imagined nature 
            Is said to have the characteristics of existence and non-existence. 
            Let us work through these verses with an ordinary example in mind. 
            Let us 
            consider 
            a teacup on your desk. Consider its imagined nature. As imagined, it 
            is an 
            existent -- indeed independently, substantially existent -- teacup 
            entirely 
            distinct from and 
            independent from your mind and mental processes. It endures through 
            time, and 
            has a 
            nature all its own. Hence existence, in a very strong sense, is part 
            of its 
            imagined nature. 
            On the other hand, when we move up one level in the dialectic, and 
            see that 
            this is 
            merely an imagined nature -- merely the way the cup appears to a 
            consciousness, 
            we see 
            that the cup that so appears -- the imagined cup itself -- does not 
            exist at 
            all, just as no 
            water exists in the mirage. In this sense, the very fact that the 
            cup-as-imagined is only 
            imagined means that though it is imagined as existent, in fact it is 
            
            non-existent. Insofar as 
            we simply imagine the cup, we imagine an existent cup. Insofar as we 
            become 
            reflexively aware of that act of imagination, the cup we imagine 
            disappears. 
            12. Since it exists as an illusory entity 
            And is non-existent in the way it appears 
            The other-dependent nature 
            Is said to have the characteristics of existence and non-existence. 
            Now, consider the same teacup from the standpoint of its 
            other-dependent 
            nature: 
            from this standpoint, the cup exists as an entity dependent upon the 
            mind. The 
            cup 
            so-considered certainly exists: it exists as a mental phenomenon -- 
            as a 
            representation. 
            On the other hand, we can ask what the objective character(23) of 
            that 
            representation 
            is. Then the answer is simple, and takes us back to the imagined 
            nature: the 
            cup 
            considered objectively is the old, real, independent cup, which, 
            when we 
            understand it 
            from the standpoint of the dependent nature, does not exist at all, 
            just in 
            virtue of the 
            fact that from this standpoint it is dependent. So, from the 
            perspective of the 
            dependent 
            nature, the cup -- the dependent mental phenomenon we mistake for a 
            real 
            cup -- like 
            the refraction pattern we mistake for water -- exists. But that 
            putative real 
            cup which is the content of that mental episode does not. 
            13. Since it is the non-existence of duality 
            And exists as non-duality 
            The consummate nature 
            Is said to have the characteristics of existence and non-existence. 
            Now we come to the consummate nature of our cup. The cup we have 
            been 
            considering all along whether from the standpoint of the imagined or 
            the 
            dependent nature, is, in an important and common sense, dual in 
            nature. In its 
            imagined nature it is an independent object of mind, and so is 
            distinct from the 
            subject which apprehends it. But in its dependent nature, as an 
            episode of mind, 
            it is still, as a mere episode or mental act, distinct from the mind 
            which is 
            its agent or subject. In the consummate nature, this duality 
            vanishes. For the 
            consummate nature of the cup is the very fact of its illusory status 
            -- that it 
            is nothing other than aspect of mind. Hence the apparent, dual, cup 
            is, in its 
            consummate nature (or, equivalently -- from the point of view of one 
            of 
            consummate attainment) utterly non-existence. But that non-duality 
            really exists 
            That is the final nature of the cup.(24) And in this sense, the 
            consummate 
            nature embraces both existence and non-existence -- the 
            non-existence of the cup 
            as dual is its true existence as non-dually related to the mind 
            apprehending it. 
            This consideration of duality and non-duality as the mediators of 
            existence and 
            non-existence in the consummate forms the bridge to the 
            consideration of duality 
            and non-duality per se in the three natures. 
            14. Moreover, since as imagined there are two aspects, 
            But existence and non-existence are unitary, 
            The nature imagined by the ignorant 
            Is said to the both dual and unitary. 
            For a thing to exist as imagined, and for it not to exist in the way 
            it appears, 
            are both diametrically opposed and identical, depending on how one 
            conceives 
            them. For on the one hand, they represent existence and 
            non-existence, the most 
            opposed of properties. In that sense, the imagined nature is 
            thoroughly dual, 
            encompassing both of these in virtue of the more fundamental 
            subject-object 
            duality it represents. That more fundamental duality gives rise both 
            to the 
            imagined existence of the object experience, and, when seen for what 
            it is -- a 
            mere illusion, the non-existence of that object in the way that it 
            appears. On 
            the other hand, to exist as imagined just is not to exist in the way 
            a thing 
            appears. In this sense the mode of existence and the mode of 
            non-existence 
            of the imagined nature -- of a thing as it is imagined -- are the 
            same, and are 
            non-dually related. And this non-duality is rooted in the more 
            fundamental 
            non-duality that emerges when we see from a higher standpoint that a 
            thing as 
            imagined is merely mental, and hence not distinct from mind. Hence 
            the imagined 
            nature is both dual and 
            unitary, depending on how it is conceived. And the object as 
            imagined is 
            experienced dually in a non-reflective consciousness, but non-dually 
            by more 
            accomplished consciousness reflecting on that experience. 
            15. Since as an object of thought it is dual, 
            But as a mere appearance it is unitary, 
            The other-dependent nature 
            Is said to be both dual unitary. 
            We can say pretty much the same thing about the other-dependent 
            nature. A 
            phenomenon understood as other-dependent is both dependent upon the 
            mind that 
            represents it and is also a mere appearance of, an content of, that 
            consciousness In that sense the object is no different from that 
            consciousness. Hence this nature, too, is both dual and unitary, 
            depending on 
            how it is conceived. 
            16. Since it is the essence of dual entities 
            And is unitary non-duality, 
            The consummate nature 
            Is said to be both dual and unitary. 
            The unity of duality and non-duality is perhaps a bit less 
            compelling in the 
            consummate nature, For the consummate nature is virtually defined by 
            its 
            non-duality and by the fact that from its perspective all duality is 
            erased. 
            But Vasubandhu is concerned to argue that it, too, in a sense, 
            participates in 
            duality, and this for two reasons. The first, and least interesting, 
            is his 
            obvious drive for poetic symmetry in the exposition. The second 
            reason is a bit 
            more philosophically interesting: the pair duality/unity is itself a 
            duality and 
            so should, from the standpoint of the consummate, be overcome. So to 
            say that 
            the consummate nature is non-dual, or unitary as opposed to being 
            dual would be 
            self defeating. So Vasubandhu needs to achieve a kind of sublation 
            of duality 
            and non duality in the consummate. And he achieves this by noting 
            that while the 
            consummate nature itself may be non-dual, it is nonetheless the 
            nature of dual 
            entities -- entities that appear in their imagined nature, in virtue 
            of their 
            other-dependent nature. Inasmuch as it is nature of dual entities, 
            then, the 
            consummate nature can be said to be dual. 
            17. The imagined and the other-dependent 
            Are said to be characterized by misery (due to ignorant carving). 
            The consummate is free of 
            The characteristic of desire. 
            This verse introduces the discussion in 17-21 of the sense in which 
            the three 
            natures are identical to one another despite their apparent 
            differences in 
            characteristic. Vasubandhu begins by emphasizing the prima facie 
            ontological 
            and ontological and soteriological gulf separating the imagined and 
            the 
            other-dependent from the consummate: the former are on the side of 
            samsara; 
            the latter is on the side of nirvana. The former two represent the 
            aspects of 
            phenomena apparent to a mind beset by primal ignorance, and hence by 
            the 
            suffering it engenders; therefore also the aspects responsible for 
            the 
            perpetuation of that ignorance and craving on the vicious circle of 
            ignorance, 
            grasping and suffering that constitutes cylic existence. The third, 
            on the other 
            hand, represents that aspect of phenomena apparent to a mind that 
            has 
            transcended all of that, and the aspect that conduces to the 
            alleviation of 
            suffering.(25) But, as we shall see, this prima facie ontological, 
            epistemological gulf will be obliterated in the final union of the 
            three 
            natures. 
            18. Since the former has the nature of a false duality 
            And the latter is the non-existence of that nature, 
            The imagined and the consummate 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            Vasubandhu now begins the task of unifying the three natures as 
            three mutually 
            implicative aspects of a single reality. He begins with the relation 
            between the 
            imagined and the consummate: the imagined nature is essentially 
            dualistic, in 
            that it involves an ontic distinction between subject and object; 
            but seen as 
            imagined that duality is in fact seen to be non-existent. But the 
            non-existence 
            of that duality is exactly what the consummate nature is. The 
            imagined nature 
            and the consummate nature are hence, from an ontological 
            perspective, not 
            different from one another. The difference is only apparent, 
            representing a 
            difference in perspective, rather than one of reality. The next 
            verse makes the 
            same point in the converse direction. 
            19. Since the former has the nature of non-duality, 
            And the latter has the nature of non-existent duality, 
            The consummate and the imagined 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            20. Since the former is deceptive in the way it appears, 
            And the latter has the nature of its not being that way, 
            The other-dependent and the consummate 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            Verses 20 and 21 are devoted to establishing the identity of the 
            consummate and 
            the other-dependent natures. The point in verse 20 is parallel to 
            that made with 
            respect to the imagined nature. The dependent nature is deceptive, 
            in that 
            phenomena that are so dependent appear to be distinct from -- 
            although dependent 
            upon -- the subject. But when that natures is seen, from a higher 
            perspective, 
            to be only dependent, but to be the fact of being merely mental, and 
            hence 
            non-different from the mind on which the phenomena depend. that 
            understanding 
            is the understanding of the consummate nature of things. Again, the 
            difference 
            between the natures is revealed to be not ontological in character, 
            but merely 
            perspectival. 
            21. Since the former has the nature of a non-existent duality, 
            And the latter is its non-existence in the way it appears, 
            The other-dependent and the consummate 
            Are said not to be different in characteristic. 
            The parallel to the relation between the imagined and the consummate 
            natures is 
            emphasized in verse 21. The other-dependent, like the imagined, is 
            dualistic in 
            character. But when things experienced in their other-dependent 
            nature are seen 
            to be so experienced, the duality vanishes, and the non-existence of 
            that 
            duality is the consummate nature itself. The apparent difference 
            between the 
            natures is hence, for Vasubandhu, a difference not in the object -- 
            in the 
            ontological character of phenomena, but rather in the subject -- and 
            hence not 
            a difference in nature, but a difference in experience of a single 
            triune 
            nature. 
            22. But conventionally, 
            The natures are explained in order and 
            Based on that one enters them 
            In a particular order, it is said. 
            Nonetheless, though the three natures are at a deeper level a unity, 
            
            pedagogically they 
            from a hierarchy. There is an order in which they must be presented 
            for the 
            sake of clarity and soteriological efficacy. This is the topic of 
            verse 22-25. 
            23. The imagined is entirely conventional. 
            The other-dependent is attached to convention. 
            The consummate, cutting convention, 
            Is said to be a different nature. 
            The imagined nature is the easiest to present first. Is is the way 
            that 
            ordinary, unreflective persons represent things. The 
            other-dependent, while 
            constituting a more sophisticated view of things, remain at a 
            conventional 
            level. It, however, has real soteriological use, starting the 
            process of 
            freeing the mind the tyranny of convention and fundamental 
            ignorance, and 
            providing a bridge to a more transcendent view. Finally, awareness 
            of the 
            consummate nature allows the move to a fully awakened view of 
            reality. 
            24. Having first entered into the non-existence of duality 
            Which is the dependent, one understands 
            The non-existent duality 
            Which is the imagined. 
            On the other hand, Vasubandhu claims, the order of understanding the 
            non-dual 
            characters of the two conventional natures is reversed. It is easier 
            to see 
            that the dependent nature is non-dual. For once one has ascended to 
            an awareness 
            of this nature, and hence of the multiplicity of the natures of 
            phenomena and 
            of their mind-dependence, it is possible to see phenomena as 
            non-dually related 
            to mind. One can then reflect on the imagined nature -- initially 
            experienced as 
            a dualistic relation to appearances -- and see it, too, as non-dual 
            in character 
            in virtue of the identity in ontic status between subject and object 
            in that 
            nature. One must bear in mind that the point being made in this and 
            the 
            surrounding verses is a pedagogical point: as long as one only 
            experiences the 
            imagined nature, it is hard to see things non-dualistically. That 
            ability is 
            made possible by the understanding represented by awareness of the 
            other-dependent nature, and then reflectively applies to the 
            other-dependent. 
            25. Then one enters the consummate. 
            Its nature is the non-existence of duality. 
            Therefore it is explained 
            To be both existent and non-existent. 
            Finally, once one has thoroughly understood both of the merely 
            conventional 
            natures, including their apparent dualities, but the unreality of 
            each duality, 
            one sees that all phenomena are both apparently dual, and ultimately 
            non-dual. 
            That is their consummate nature. Realizing this nature is the 
            consequence of a 
            complete understanding of the other two. 
            26. These three natures. 
            Have the characteristics of being non-cognizable and non-dual. 
            One is completely non-existent; the second is therefore 
            non-existent. 
            The third has the nature of that non-existence. 
            This verse sums up the result of the previous two discussions. Going 
            "from top 
            to bottom", the consummate nature is non-cognizable because all 
            cognition, as 
            discursive, is inescapably dualistic; the other two natures are 
            non-dual when 
            seen from that perspective, despite the duality engendered from 
            within the 
            perspective from any higher perspective. Therefore, the 
            other-dependent nature, 
            being the dependence of a non-existent entity on the mind, is also 
            non-existent 
            when seen from the standpoint of the consummate. And the consummate 
            is just the 
            fact of the non-existence of the first two. Thus, Vasubandhu 
            concludes, despite 
            the vast difference in the phenomenological character of the three 
            perspectives 
            from which phenomena have these three natures, the natures 
            themselves are 
            identical, joined in the object in virtue of its ideality. 
            The next section of the text develops the famous simile of the 
            illusory 
            elephant conjured by the stage magician. This is in fact the only 
            portion of 
            this text regularly cited in later polemical and hermeneutic 
            discussions of 
            cittamatra philosophy by Tibetan commentators:(26) 
            27. Like an elephant that appears 
            Through the power of magician's 
            mantra -- Only the percept appears, 
            The elephant is completely non-existent. 
            The magician, allegedly using a mantra, caused the astonished 
            audience to see 
            an apparition of an elephant. But, we are assured, there really is 
            no elephant. 
            The illusion is engendered purely by the skill of the magician and 
            the 
            gullibility of the audience. 
            28. The imagined nature is the elephant; 
            The other-dependent nature is the visual percept; 
            The non-existence of the elephant therein 
            Is explained to be the consummate. 
            Now we can see the diverse aspects of subjectivity marked by the 
            three natures 
            as well as the ontological unity of the natures in the object (or 
            putative 
            object) they characterize. The non-existent elephant -- the apparent 
            object of 
            perception -- is the elephant. The deluded audience believes it to 
            exist, in 
            virtue of decidedly non-pachidermic causes and their own deluded 
            ignorance. But 
            nothing in fact exists in the way the elephant appears. But there is 
            indeed a 
            percept -- not a living, breathing elephant -- but a psychological 
            episode 
            brought into an sustained in existence in dependence on numerous 
            conditions. 
            This corresponds to the dependent nature. And the fact that there is 
            no 
            elephant in this percept -- that the elephant is completely 
            non-existent and 
            the percept is purely mental -- is the consummate nature. 
            Note that this is a simile, and not a literal model of perception. 
            What is 
            crucial here is that to a naive observer, the hallucinated elephant 
            appears as 
            real and independent. To one "in the know" there is a real percept, 
            but one 
            which is decidedly not an independent elephant, and whose existence 
            is entirely 
            dependent on the state of mind of the member of the audience. And 
            finally, the 
            full story is that there simply is no elephant at all -- not even 
            one in 
            perception -- only hallucination which is purely mental and entirely 
            in the mind 
            of the audience member. Just as the imagined nature of my teacup is 
            that it is 
            an independent object; the dependent nature is that is is my mental 
            representation and not an independent external object; and its 
            consummate 
            nature is its complete non-existence from a transcendent point of 
            view. 
            29. Through the root consciousness 
            The nonexistent duality appears. 
            But since the duality is completely non-existent, 
            There is only a percept. 
            Just a through the force of the magician's incantations and 
            manipulations the 
            illusory elephant appears, through the force of our own mental 
            predispoditions 
            the percept appears. But just as the elephant is purely 
            hallucinatory, the 
            percept is purely mental. 
            30. The root consciousness is like the mantra. 
            Reality can be compared to the wood. 
            Imagination is like the perception of the elephant. 
            Duality can be seen as the elephant. 
            The psychological basis of appearances, for Vasubandhu and his 
            cittamatra 
            followers, is the root consciousness, and the potentials it contains 
            for 
            experiences. The mantra -- the magician, in this analogy, has a prop 
            -- a 
            piece of wood. (How this trick is actually performed is utterly 
            mysterious at 
            this point.) So, what appears to be an elephant is actually a piece 
            of wood, 
            transformed by the magician into an apparitional elephant. Likewise, 
            in 
            experience, what appears to be an independent object is in fact a 
            merely 
            mental episode, caused by the actualization of latencies in the root 
            
            consciousness to appear as independent nature, since that nature 
            gives us the 
            perceived object as a mere percept as opposed to as the object it 
            appears to be. 
            The imagined nature, on the other hand, is analogous to the 
            hallucinated 
            elephant, and the non-existent duality is like the intentional 
            object of that 
            hallucination -- the non-existent elephant. 
            The concluding verses of the text are devoted to its soteriological 
            implications. For cittamatra philosophy, like any Buddhist system, 
            is 
            soteriological in intent. The point of the system is to gain 
            liberation from 
            the delusions, attachments and suffering of samsara in order to be 
            able to 
            assist other sentient beings in accomplishing the same. From the 
            cittamatra 
            point of view, the root delusion is the taking the imagined nature 
            of things to 
            be their reality, and to fail to appreciate the other two natures, 
            the identity 
            of the three natures, and hence to fail to achieve the viewpoint 
            represented 
            by the consummate which reveals the world as it is. 
            31. When one understand how things are, 
            Perfect knowledge, abandonment, 
            And accomplishment -- 
            These three characteristics are simultaneously achieved. 
            To understand how things are is to understand all three natures 
            simultaneously 
            and in their correct relations to one another. This amounts to 
            perfect knowledge 
            of the ontology of the world and of the character of one's own 
            subjectivity. 
            That is to abandon attachment to the imagined phenomena craved by 
            one who 
            believes them to be real as they appear in imagination, and that is 
            to 
            accomplish the goal of perfect insight into the nature of things and 
            consequent 
            freedom from the craving which is the necessary condition of 
            ignorance and 
            afflicted action. 
            32. Knowledge is non-perception; 
            Abandonment is non-appearance; 
            Attainment is accomplished through non-dual perception. 
            That is direct manifestation. 
            Perfect knowledge of this kind is non-perception in the sense that 
            it is 
            objectless, for 
            the objects of ordinary perception are seen to be illusory, and the 
            duality of 
            perceiver 
            and perceived that structures perception is transcended. Abandonment 
            of 
            commitment 
            and attachment to imagined phenomena is achieved through the 
            transcendence of 
            instinctive assent to the imagined nature. The attainment of freedom 
            is 
            accomplished 
            through the direct, immediate understanding of the unity of the 
            three 
            natures, and hence the non-dual awareness of all phenomena in their 
            consummate nature. For one who has attained this kind of knowledge, 
            Vasubandhu claims, this cognitive relation to things is direct, 
            intuitive, 
            and immediate -- not the consequence of constant philosophical 
            analysis -- but the primary way of taking up with the world, albeit 
            achieved 
            through long analysis and practice. 
            33. Through the non-perception of the elephant, 
            The vanishing of its percept occurs; 
            And so does the perception of the piece of wood. 
            This is how it is in the magic show. 
            Here Vasubandhu returns to the analogy in order to explain the 
            structure of this 
            accomplishment. When one sees through the trick -- when one stops 
            being taken 
            in by the show -- one stops seeing the elephant, and the percept 
            vanishes. 
            One no longer sees 
            the piece of wood as an elephant at all. All of the illusion ceases. 
            
            34. In the same way through the non-perception of duality 
            There is the vanishing of duality. 
            When it vanishes completely, 
            Non-dual awareness arises. 
            Similarly, through an accomplished perception of things in accord 
            with the 
            three-nature 
            theory one stops seeing the dualistically represented phenomena. 
            Those 
            things, as they are seen by an ordinary, deluded consciousness, 
            completely 
            disappear. One sees through the 
            show of ordinary experience, and the illusion ceases. One sees 
            things simply as 
            they are, 
            without duality, without ascribing them independent reality, as 
            having the 
            triune three 
            natures, each understood fully from the standpoint of the 
            consummate. 
            35. Through perceiving correctly, 
            Through seeing the non-referentiality of mental states, 
            Through following the three wisdoms, 
            One will effortlessly attain liberation. 
            This understanding has, Vasubandhu here announces, soteriological 
            consequences. In virtue of coming to understand that one's mental 
            states do 
            not represent an independent reality, and through understanding 
            fully the 
            three natures and their relations to 
            one another, attachment to objects as genuinely real, and as 
            legitimate 
            objects of craving, ceases. The are only dream-objects, nothing to 
            take 
            seriously, including both 
            objects perceived as external, and one's self as it appears to 
            oneself. The 
            attendant 
            cessation of grasping and of attachment is precisely the cessation 
            denominated 
            by the 
            term "nirvana". 
            36. Through the perception of mind-only 
            One achieves the non-perception of objects; 
            Through the non-perception of objects 
            There is also the non-perception of mind. 
            This verse emphasizes the connection between the release from 
            attachment to 
            external objects and the release from attachment of self. One begins 
            the 
            cittamatra 
            analysis by seeing all phenomena as purely mental. This dissipates 
            the view that 
            external phenomena are real. But with this realization comes the 
            realization 
            that the 
            mind we experience -- the self we cherish -- is every bit as much an 
            object for 
            us (albeit 
            of inner and not outer sense) and so is every bit as unreal as the 
            outer objects 
            to which 
            it is so easy to become attached. Our self-attachment is hence 
            revealed by this 
            analysis 
            to be every bit as much the product of ontological delusion as is 
            out 
            attachment to 
            external phenomena. 
            37. Through the non-duality of perception, 
            Arises the perception of the fundamental nature of reality. 
            Through the perception of the fundamental nature of reality 
            Arises the perception of the radiant. 
            This realization is the full understanding of the three nature 
            theory and its 
            implications. 
            The fundamental nature of reality is its threefold character, and 
            the unity of 
            this threefold character in the ultimate non-duality of all that 
            appears as 
            dual. The experience of the world in this way is, Vasubandhu claims, 
            a 
            radiant, or totally illuminating gnosis. 
            38. Through the perception of the radiant, 
            And through achieving the three supreme Buddha-bodies, 
            And through possessing bodhi: 
            Having achieved this, the sage will benefit him/herself and others. 
            The deep insight embodied in this gnosis, coupled with the 
            altruistic aspiration 
            to attain 
            liberation for the sake of other sentient beings enables the 
            practitioner, 
            through physical 
            acts (the use of the form-body), through the blissful detachment 
            from suffering 
            that 
            enables one to take the welfare of others fully into account (the 
            fruits of the 
            enjoyment-body) and through thorough understanding (the truth-body) 
            to be 
            maximally 
            efficacious on behalf of others. 
            This brief text hence articulates all of the principal features of 
            cittamatra 
            philosophy: 
            its thoroughgoing idealism; the three nature theory of the ontology 
            of 
            representation 
            and of the phenomenology entailed by that idealism; the 
            understanding of 
            non-duality 
            and emptiness in which that theory issues; and the soteriological 
            consequences 
            both of 
            the three nature ontology and of the full understanding of the 
            theory 
            itself.(27) There 
            certainly are briefer expositions, more detailed expositions of this 
            system in 
            the classical 
            literature, but perhaps none so elegant and perspicuous. 
            NOTES 
            (1) My reading of this text has developed as a result of many 
            conversation with 
            and instruction from 
            teachers, students and colleagues. I thank in particular Janet 
            Gyatso for 
            extended discussion of 
            cittamatra philosophy in general and this text in particular, the 
            Ven. Geshe 
            Yeshes Thap-khas for 
            several teaching sessions, the Ven. Gen Lobsang Gyatso for several 
            useful 
            conversations and Ms 
            Karen Meyers for a number of spirited discussions of this text and 
            of cittamatra 
            philosophy in 
            general. Dr Moira Nicholls read an earlier version and made a number 
            of useful 
            suggestions. Mr 
            Jens Schleiter has made many very helpful suggestions regarding both 
            the 
            translation and 
            commentary. Both are much improved as a consequence. I also an 
            anonymous 
            reviewer for 
            Asian Philosophy for pointing out lacunae in an earlier version. 
            Thanks also to 
            Sri Yeshi Tashi 
            Shastri and Mr Jamyang Norbu Gurung for research assistance. 
            (2) See, e.g. Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamikakarika [Garfield, J. (1995) 
            Fundamental 
            Wisdom of the 
            Middle way: Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika (New York, Oxford 
            University Press) 
            or Candrakirti's Madhyamakavatara [Huntington, C. & Wangchen, Geshe 
            N. (1989) 
            The Emptiness of Emptiness: Candrakirti's Madhyamakavatara]. 
            (3) See also Vasubandhu's Madhyanta-vibhaga-bhasya and 
            Trimsikakarika in 
            Kochumuttom, T. 
            (1982) A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience: A New Translation and 
            Interpretation 
            of the Works of 
            Vasubandhu the Yogacarin (Delhi, Motilal Banarsidaas), and Anacker, 
            S. (1984) 
            Seven Works of 
            Vasubandhu: The Buddhist Psychological Doctor (Delhi, Motilal 
            Banarsidass) for 
            further expositions 
            of this view. 
            (4) While such comparisons will prove useful, and while the 
            affinities are real, 
            one must be 
            very careful not to push the comparisons too far. There is a 
            specifically 
            Buddhist context to 
            Vasubandhu's idealism, and the different philosophical milieus of 
            medieval India 
            and modern 
            Europe generate distinct philosophical positions and moves. It is 
            well beyond 
            the scope of this 
            commentary to address all of the relevant similarities and 
            differences, or even 
            to spell out all of 
            Vasubandhu's arguments or system. See Garfield, J. (forthcoming) 
            Western 
            idealism through 
            Indian eyes: Reading Berkeley, Kant and Schopenhauer through 
            Vasubandhu, Sophia, 
            for more 
            on comparison between Vasubandhu's idealism and Western versions of 
            that 
            doctrine. 
            (5) This may be due to the fact that this text was written when 
            Vasubandhu was 
            quite advanced in 
            years. It was probably composed at Ayodhya during the last year or 
            two of his 
            life. 
            (6) Compare, for instance, the presentation of the three natures in 
            the 
            Samdhinirmocana-sutra in 
            which these ontological claims are completely absent. 
            (7) See Legs bshad snyings po, translated in Thurman, R. (1984) 
            Tsong Khapa's 
            Speech of Gold in the 
            Essence of True Eloquence (Princeton, Princeton University Press), 
            esp. pp. 
            223-230. 
            (8) See sTong thun chen mo, translated in Cabezon, J. (1992) A Dose 
            of Emptiness 
            (Albany, State 
            University of New York Press), esp. pp. 39-43. 
            (9) See Garfield, J. (1997) Three natures and three 
            naturelessnesses: comments 
            on cittamatra 
            conceptual categories, Journal of Indian Philosophy and Religion, 
            for more on 
            Cittamatra 
            doxography and on the relations between the three natures and three 
            naturelessnesses. 
            (10) Translated in Huntingdon (1989), see esp. pp. 162-168. 
            (11) The present translation is from the Tibetan text. The principal 
            version 
            used is that in the Peking 
            edition of the Tibetan canon (Si 12a-14a). The Sde dge edition was 
            used for 
            comparison, and is 
            in complete concordance. Anacker, op. cit., and Wood (1991) Mind 
            Only: A 
            Philosophical and 
            Doctrinal Analysis of the Vijnanavada (Honolulu, University of 
            Hawaii Press), 
            each reprint the 
            original Sanskrit text. 
            (12) Again, it is interesting to contrast this presentation with 
            that of the 
            Samdhinirmocana-sutra where 
            this dependence is explicitly characterized as dependence on other 
            non-mental 
            causes and 
            conditions. Vasubandhu is clearly developing an idealistic position 
            that 
            contrasts with the 
            strikingly non-idealistic ontology of the Samdhinirmocana-sutra. It 
            is in large 
            part due to 
            doxographic imperatives to unify the Yogacara corpus theoretically 
            that so many 
            Tibetans read the 
            Samdhinirmocana-sutra as idealistic and that so many contemporary 
            Western 
            scholars have lately 
            argued that Vasubandhu is not an idealist. (See Garfield 
            [forthcoming], op. 
            cit., for more on 
            this.) Both imperatives should be resisted, as the tradition is 
            internally 
            quite diverse. 
            (13) Kochumuttom, op. cit., Thurman, op. cit., Wood, op. cit., 
            Powers, J. (1995) 
            Wisdom of the 
            Buddha: The Samdhinirmocana Mahayana Sotra (Berkeley, Dharma Press), 
            Anacker, 
            op. cit., 
            Nagao, G. (1991) Madhyamaka and Yogacara (Albany, State University 
            of New York 
            Press) and 
            Cabezon, op. cit., respectively. 
            (14) Contrast this with the standard presentation of cittamatra 
            metaphysics in 
            Geluk-pa doxography, 
            following Sthiramati, according to which the second and third are 
            real, but the 
            first -- the imagined 
            nature -- is completely unreal. See Tsong Khapa in Thurman, op. 
            cit., pp. 
            223-230 and mKhas 
            grub in Cabezon, op. cit., pp. 47-61. See also Meyers, K. (1995) 
            Empty talk: 
            Tsong Khapa's 
            elucidation of the Buddha's intention as a matter of semantics, 
            Amherst, 
            Hampshire College 
            Division III thesis, ch. 2. 
            (15) See Kant, I. (1965) Critique of Pure Reason, N. Kemp-Smith 
            (transl.) (New 
            York, St Martin's 
            Press), b275-276 and Berkeley, G. (1954) Three Dialogues Between 
            Hylas and 
            Philonous, 
            C. Turbayne (Ed.) (Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill). 
            (16) Schopenhauer, A. (1974) The Fourfold Root of the Principle of 
            Sufficient 
            Reason, E. F. J. Payne 
            (Transl.) (LaSalle, Open Court), pp. 273, ff, Schopenhauer, A. 
            (1969) The World 
            as Will and 
            Representation, E. F. J. Payne (Transl.) (New York, Dover), Section 
            4. See also 
            "Criticism of the 
            Kantian Philosophy". 
            (17) Schopenhauer, (1969) Sections 19, 23-24. 
            (18) This is not to say that Schopenhauer charges Kant with the 
            failure to 
            postulate a 
            nouemenon -- only that he charges Kant with the failure to see that 
            this 
            noumenal character is a third nature of 
            the object, one which is knowable immediately, without 
            subject-object duality. 
            Again, in this 
            respect Vasubandhu's idealism is far closer to Schopenhauer's than 
            it is to 
            Kant's. I thank Dr 
            Moira Nicholls for pointing out the need for clarity on this point. 
            (19) See the analysis of time as the form of inner sense and hence 
            of the 
            empirical character of 
            self-knowledge in the transcendental Aesthetic, Critique of Pure 
            Reason, 
            b155-159. 
            (20) It is not, however -- to put it mildly -- at all obvious that 
            these 
            etymological claims are at all 
            accurate. 
            (21) Again, the anticipation of Kant's account o empirical 
            self-knowledge is 
            striking. 
            (22) This gets complex and leads to an analysis of samsara itself, 
            and the sense 
            in which everything in 
            samsara can be said to be afflicted -- to be caused by and to be a 
            cause of 
            suffering, and in a deeper 
            sense to have suffering and primal ignorance as part of its very 
            ontological 
            structure; and then to 
            an analysis of a specifically Yogacara understanding of samsara. But 
            that is 
            beyond the scope of 
            this commentary. 
            (23) In the scholastic or Cartesian sense -- the character of the 
            mental object 
            itself. 
            (24) Note how this account of the ultimate nature of a phenomenon 
            contrasts with 
            that given by 
            Madhyamika philosophers such as Nagarjuna or Candrakirti, according 
            to whom not 
            even the 
            emptiness of the cup can be said to exist in this sense. It is at 
            this crucial 
            point in ontology that 
            Cittamatra and Madhyamaka are utterly discontinuous. See SIDERITS, 
            M. (1996) On 
            the 
            continuity thesis, Australia-New Zealand Joint Religious Studies 
            Conference, 
            Christchurch, Garfield, 
            op. cit., note 2, but see Nagao, op. cit., note 13, for a contrary 
            view. 
            (25) This contrasts once again with the standard Geluk-pa view 
            according to 
            which the important 
            ontological divide is between the imagined nature and the other two. 
            On this 
            view, the imagined 
            nature is wholly false, while the other-dependent and consummate 
            natures are 
            both truly existent. 
            (26) See, for instance, mKhas grub in Cabezon, op. cit., note 13, p. 
            50. 
            (27) The one significant ontological doctrine associated with 
            cittamatra 
            philosophy that does not make 
            an appearance here is the theory of the three naturelessnesses 
            (trinihsvabhava/ngo bo nyid med gsum) 
            that takes centre stage in the Samdhinirmocana-sutra. In 
            Trimsika-karika 
            Vasubandhu connects 
            this doctrine to trisvabhava theory, arguing that each nature is 
            natureless in 
            one of these senses. 
            Sthiramati, in his commentary on this text, argues that in fact the 
            three 
            natures and the three 
            naturelessnesses are the same -- a view adopted by such Tibetan 
            exegetes as 
            Tsong Khapa and 
            mKhas grub. This is not a view that Vasubandhu ever articulates, 
            however, and 
            while he makes 
            use of the trinihsvabhava in explicating emptiness in 
            Madhyanta-vibhaga-bhasya 
            it is not, on his 
            view, a doctrine specifically connected to idealism, and so has no 
            role in the 
            present text. See 
            Garfield, op. cit., note 9, for more on the relation between the 
            three natures 
            and the three 
            naturelessnesses.