Psychoanalysis, Buddhism and the person. (include sresponse)(comment on article by Jonathan Spencer, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, vol 3, p. 693)
Alexandra Ourossoff
Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute Vol.4 No.4 Dec 1998 pp.795-798
COPYRIGHT @ Royal Anthropological Institute (UK)
¡@
There is as yet no commonly accepted theoretical understanding of the specific social reality of unconscious experience. So it is a matter of some interest when an article appears in this Journal that sets out to compare the psychoanalytic concept of the person with an apparently similar concept found within the Buddhist canon (Spencer, J. Fatima and the enchanted toffees: an essay in contingency, narrative and therapy. J. Roy. anthrop. Inst. (N.S.) 3, 693-710). The ostensible aim of Spencer's article is to compare Buddhist and Freudian ideas about the person and suggest that concepts that emphasize contingency may be particularly useful in situations of acute personal affliction. He may be right. The problem is that the notion of a contingent self bears no relation to the Freudian concept of the person. This misunderstanding, combined with a lack of ethnographic evidence showing how the concept relates to social practice in the Western context, would appear to leave little basis for his comparison. Spencer extracts the 'psychoanalytic' concept of the person from a body of theory that is becoming increasingly influential. Its most widely read representatives are Paul Ricoeur, Richard Rorty and Adam Phillips. What unites these authors, despite their considerable differences, is an indifference towards the highly variable emotional relations through which each person's unconscious world is realized. The motive implicit in their criteria of irrelevance presumably unconscious - is to promote a collapse of the subtle and complex process of unconscious formation into the present. One consequence of abstracting from the body of psychoanalytic theory which does acknowledge emotional variations between family histories is an acute awareness of the extraordinary degree to which the child's emotional struggle with the social world determines the conscious life of the adult. This awareness, taken together with a rich understanding of culture, leaves no room for human agency and the illusion of a self-directed consciousness that the concept of agency invariably assumes. Spencer's principal objective seems to be to ward off the consequences of this awareness. He suggests that the same person may hold two concepts of the self. The first is the unstable or contingent self, which in the Western context, he argues, is derived from Freudian theory and is conceptualized as the product of a 'concatenation of random events'. The second is the stable self, 'a robustly bounded individual' associated with the legal concept of the person and which entails self-directed consciousness. Spencer (p. 695) supports his version of the psychoanalytic concept of the person with an extract from the last page of Freud's study of Leonardo (which Freud never counted as one of his case histories): If one considers chance to be unworthy of determining our fate, it is simply a relapse into the pious view of the universe which Leonardo himself was on the way to overcoming when he wrote that the sun does not move ... We are all too ready to forget that in fact everything to do with our life is chance, from our origin out of the meeting of the spermatozoon and ovum onwards. But the full quotation reveals a somewhat different meaning: If one considers chance to be unworthy of determining our fate, it is simply a relapse into the pious view of the universe which Leonardo himself was on the way to overcoming when he wrote that the sun does not move. We naturally feel hurt that a just God and a kindly providence do not protect us better from such influences during the most defenceless period of our lives. At the same time we are all too ready to forget that in fact everything to do with our life is chance, from our origin out of the meeting of the spermatozoon and ovum onwards - chance which nevertheless has a share in the law and necessity of nature, and which merely lacks any connection with our wishes and illusions. The apportioning of the determining factors of our life between the 'necessities' of our constitution and the 'chances' of our childhood may still be uncertain in detail; but in general it is no longer possible to doubt the importance precisely of the first years of our childhood. We all still show too little respect for Nature which (in the obscure words of Leonardo which recall Hamlet's lines) 'is full of countless causes ['ragioni'] that never enter experience'. Every one of us human beings corresponds to one of the countless experiments in which these ragioni of nature force their way into experience (Freud 1963: 186). It is clear Freud is arguing against a supernatural explanation of the not uncommon feeling of being a slave to chance and in favour of an explanation in terms of historical causes that do not enter conscious experience. Closing his eyes to the all-important sentences allows Spencer, following Rorty, to equate events not the result of conscious design, 'that merely lack any connection with our wishes and illusions' with events that have no cause. The effect of this simple equivocation is to erase both the content and intention of Freud's work. One does not have to be a convinced Freudian to recognize that Freud was attempting to unveil the underlying principles of neurosis (which for him was a relative concept) without denying the diversity of its forms of expression, the uniqueness that is, of the individual. Reducing the complex principles of unconscious processes to a series of random (unintelligible) events effectively mystifies these processes by placing them beyond our theoretical grasp. (For a far more elaborated version of this same reductive abstraction see Phillips 1993.) But it also - and this I believe is the point of the exercise - protects the idea of a self-directed consciousness by positing instability as its only alternative and thereby eliminating the possibility of a relatively stable, rational consciousness determined by unconscious necessity. The real drawback of the current wave of pseudo-synthesizing of Freudian theory is that it contributes to the foreclosing of important questions of history and culture. The comparative study of the child's emotional struggle with the social world has, for example, increased our understanding of the highly variable capacity of individuals for creativity and has led to a number of penetrating descriptions of the relation between creativity and the process of unconscious formation (see, for example, Milner 1987.) The value of this body of knowledge is its potential to allow for the progressive shift from seeing the ethnographic subject as a passive conduit of inherited cultural consciousness to seeing him/her as an independent and imaginative person, capable of the creative reworking of inherited consciousness without resorting to the illusion of intentionality (an illusion which is in serious danger of becoming permanently incorporated into the 'experience' of the ethnographic subject.) Whether or not one agrees with this particular perspective, the issue Spencer's article raises is the state of an intellectual culture willing to take seriously such a fundamental misreading of one of this century's most influential thinkers. ALEXANDRA OUTOUSSOFF London School of Economics & Political Science Freud, S. 1963. Leonardo. Harmondsworth; Penguin. Milner, M. 1987. The suppressed madness of sane men. London, New York: Routledge. Phillips, A. 1993, Contingency for beginners. Raritan 13, 54-72, Ricoeur, P. 1970. Freud and philosophy: an essay on interpretation (trans.) D. Savage. New Haven, London: Yale Univ. Press. Rorty, R. 1989. Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Univ. Press. In an excellent article a few years ago Alexandra Ouroussoff(1993) rightly castigated anthropologists for confusing the pieties of liberal political philosophy with the real idioms and actions of 'modem' people living in the 'West'. Using her own ethnography from a study of a major transnational corporation in Britain she addressed the question of the circumstances in which people 'define themselves as individuals': 'how precisely the lines of choice and constraint are drawn in a social context where people imagine themselves to be determining agents' (Ouroussoff 1993: 287). In my article I posed the question: 'in what contexts ... do "individualistic" ideas of personhood predominate and in what contexts are they downplayed or denied? When is the self most easily viewed as stable and enduring, and when is it better understood as a temporary product of an idiosyncratic history?' (1997: 694). All would seem set, then, for an interesting intellectual conversation, based on our provisional answers to these questions: in Ouroussoff's case, managers imagine themselves to be agents, workers are more candid about the constraints of structure; in my case from Sri Lanka, people normally talk as if they possess stable selves, but appeal to much more decentred, evanescent notions of subjectivity in moments of intense affliction. Already it is clear that our projects at once overlap (in the desire to problematize 'the concept of the person' through an ethnography of 'person-talk'), but also differ. Ouroussoff is concerned to expose the 'illusion of intentionality' and the impossible dichotomy between freedom and constraint on which, she says, the Western myth of the Western individual is based. I was surprised to learn that 'protecting this illusion does appear to be the principal task of Spencer's article', as I had thought that my aims were a little different. I was struck by the apparent formal similarities between Rorty's reading of Freud and the accounts I had read of the Buddhist doctrine of anatta or denial of the self. At this level of abstraction - and explicitly avoiding all appeal to what Freud (or the Buddha) 'really' meant - I found I could make some sense of my own ethnographic data from a case of spirit possession in Sri Lanka and also begin to make more sense of the strengths and weaknesses of a book that has haunted me from the time I first read it in 1981, Obeyesekere's (1981) Medusa's hair. In all this I had very little to say about agency and intention: in the Abstract I refer to spirit possession as an 'idiom of displaced agency', and later in the article I refer to the relationship between passivity and authenticity in local understandings of possession - 'any suggestion of agency or authenticity on her part would render the whole diagnosis suspect' (1997: 704). That is all I say on these topics. There is a simple reason for this reticence. Buddhist teaching on the self at once denies the reality of the self as a 'permanent, everlasting and unchanging entity' (Rahula 1967: 51), yet insists on the importance of 'intention' or 'volition' (cetana) as the motive force in its ethicized doctrine of karma (cf. Collins 1982: 201; Gombrich 1971: 244-68). The karmic force of an action depends not on the outcome of the act, but on the intention of the actor, while intention itself can never occur in a vacuum but is always 'conditioned' by its own karmic precursors. In other words, the doctrinal teaching on the person links together apparently familiar (or at least translatable) notions which might correspond to words like 'self' or 'person', 'intention' or 'agency', but does so in a quite different configuration from the one described by Ouroussoff: the self is an illusion, but intention is real. What makes the self real or illusory, in this view, is not especially an issue of intention or agency; it is rather an issue of stability or permanence. This question of stability or permanence was at the heart of my article and Rorty's reading of Freud alerted me to a possible parallel on this dimension. In particular, it allowed me to isolate one implication of Freud's work - what Rorty (1989: 30) calls his 'de-divinization' of the self - without involving my argument in the whole elaborate superstructure of Freudian metapsychology. This seemed ambitious enough for one article. Much of the confusion is a result of the different emphases in Ouroussoff's use of 'contingent' (causeless, non-necessary) and mine (changing, non-stable, it could be otherwise). My argument should be clear enough in the following passage: The Buddhist position shares a number of features with the reading of Freud put forward by Ricoeur and Rorty. Both are based on the idea of a pervasive causality, although the law of cause and effect in Buddhism (karma) is moral - good begets good and bad begets bad - whereas Freud's is disturbingly amoral. Both are based on some idea which we can gloss as 'desire' ... as a kind of final cause in the whole system. And both explicitly undermine our reassuring assumptions about our selves as stable, enduring essences, replacing them with histories of infinite potential complexity (1997: 696). Here, as elsewhere in my article, my use of the word 'history' should indicate my interest in Ouroussoff's 'important questions'. And, if one is interested in the idea of creativity without intentionality which she raises in the penultimate paragraph of her letter, I would refer her again to Obeyesekere's exemplary analysis of just these issues in Medusa's hair. Rereading Ouroussoff's comments, I have a growing sense that I have stumbled into someone else's argument. Ouroussoff's real beef would seem to be with Rorty (although a careful reading of his original words would reveal more agreement with Ouroussoff than she acknowledges), or more likely Phillips. I wish her well in these controversies, even as I would beg to be excused from my temporary role as surrogate victim, even for such luminaries as these. (Oddly enough, I disagree with them too.) What I admired in Ouroussoff's article on the illusions of the liberal tradition was the creative interplay between broad intellectual history and insightful ethnographic data. Her larger project is a serious and important one. As there are enough people out there who really do hold the views she is attacking - a small but increasingly insistent outbreak of anthropological neoliberalism has recently been spotted to the north of my office - it hardly seems necessary to impute them to someone who doesn't. JONATHAN SPENCER University of Edinburgh Collins, S. 1982. Selfless persons: imager and thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge: Univ. Press. Gombrich, R. 1971. Precept and practice: traditional Buddhism in the rural highlands of Ceylon. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Obeyesekere, G. 1981. Medusa's hair: an essay on personal symbols and religious experience. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press. Ouroussoff, A. 1993. Illusions of rationality: false premisses of the liberal tradition. Man (N.S.) 28, 281-98. Rahula, W. 1967. What the Buddha taught (2nd edn). London: Gordon Fraser. Rorty, R. 1989. Contingency. irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Univ. Press.