Psychoanalysis, Buddhism and the person. 
(include sresponse)(comment on article by Jonathan Spencer, 
Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, vol 3, p. 693)
Alexandra Ourossoff
Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute
Vol.4 No.4
Dec 1998
pp.795-798
COPYRIGHT @ Royal Anthropological Institute (UK)

¡@

            There is as yet no commonly accepted theoretical understanding of 
            the specific social reality of unconscious experience. So it is a 
            matter of some interest when an article appears in this Journal that 
            sets out to compare the psychoanalytic concept of the person with an 
            apparently similar concept found within the Buddhist canon (Spencer, 
            J. Fatima and the enchanted toffees: an essay in contingency, 
            narrative and therapy. J. Roy. anthrop. Inst. (N.S.) 3, 693-710). 
            The ostensible aim of Spencer's article is to compare Buddhist and 
            Freudian ideas about the person and suggest that concepts that 
            emphasize contingency may be particularly useful in situations of 
            acute personal affliction. He may be right. The problem is that the 
            notion of a contingent self bears no relation to the Freudian 
            concept of the person. This misunderstanding, combined with a lack 
            of ethnographic evidence showing how the concept relates to social 
            practice in the Western context, would appear to leave little basis 
            for his comparison. 
            Spencer extracts the 'psychoanalytic' concept of the person from a 
            body of theory that is becoming increasingly influential. Its most 
            widely read representatives are Paul Ricoeur, Richard Rorty and Adam 
            Phillips. What unites these authors, despite their considerable 
            differences, is an indifference towards the highly variable 
            emotional relations through which each person's unconscious world is 
            realized. The motive implicit in their criteria of irrelevance 
            presumably unconscious - is to promote a collapse of the subtle and 
            complex process of unconscious formation into the present. 
            One consequence of abstracting from the body of psychoanalytic 
            theory which does acknowledge emotional variations between family 
            histories is an acute awareness of the extraordinary degree to which 
            the child's emotional struggle with the social world determines the 
            conscious life of the adult. This awareness, taken together with a 
            rich understanding of culture, leaves no room for human agency and 
            the illusion of a self-directed consciousness that the concept of 
            agency invariably assumes. 
            Spencer's principal objective seems to be to ward off the 
            consequences of this awareness. He suggests that the same person may 
            hold two concepts of the self. The first is the unstable or 
            contingent self, which in the Western context, he argues, is derived 
            from Freudian theory and is conceptualized as the product of a 
            'concatenation of random events'. The second is the stable self, 'a 
            robustly bounded individual' associated with the legal concept of 
            the person and which entails self-directed consciousness. 
            Spencer (p. 695) supports his version of the psychoanalytic concept 
            of the person with an extract from the last page of Freud's study of 
            Leonardo (which Freud never counted as one of his case histories): 
            If one considers chance to be unworthy of determining our fate, it 
            is simply a relapse into the pious view of the universe which 
            Leonardo himself was on the way to overcoming when he wrote that the 
            sun does not move ... We are all too ready to forget that in fact 
            everything to do with our life is chance, from our origin out of the 
            meeting of the spermatozoon and ovum onwards. 
            But the full quotation reveals a somewhat different meaning: 
            If one considers chance to be unworthy of determining our fate, it 
            is simply a relapse into the pious view of the universe which 
            Leonardo himself was on the way to overcoming when he wrote that the 
            sun does not move. We naturally feel hurt that a just God and a 
            kindly providence do not protect us better from such influences 
            during the most defenceless period of our lives. At the same time we 
            are all too ready to forget that in fact everything to do with our 
            life is chance, from our origin out of the meeting of the 
            spermatozoon and ovum onwards - chance which nevertheless has a 
            share in the law and necessity of nature, and which merely lacks any 
            connection with our wishes and illusions. The apportioning of the 
            determining factors of our life between the 'necessities' of our 
            constitution and the 'chances' of our childhood may still be 
            uncertain in detail; but in general it is no longer possible to 
            doubt the importance precisely of the first years of our childhood. 
            We all still show too little respect for Nature which (in the 
            obscure words of Leonardo which recall Hamlet's lines) 'is full of 
            countless causes ['ragioni'] that never enter experience'. 
            Every one of us human beings corresponds to one of the countless 
            experiments in which these ragioni of nature force their way into 
            experience (Freud 1963: 186). 
            It is clear Freud is arguing against a supernatural explanation of 
            the not uncommon feeling of being a slave to chance and in favour of 
            an explanation in terms of historical causes that do not enter 
            conscious experience. 
            Closing his eyes to the all-important sentences allows Spencer, 
            following Rorty, to equate events not the result of conscious 
            design, 'that merely lack any connection with our wishes and 
            illusions' with events that have no cause. The effect of this simple 
            equivocation is to erase both the content and intention of Freud's 
            work. 
            One does not have to be a convinced Freudian to recognize that Freud 
            was attempting to unveil the underlying principles of neurosis 
            (which for him was a relative concept) without denying the diversity 
            of its forms of expression, the uniqueness that is, of the 
            individual. Reducing the complex principles of unconscious processes 
            to a series of random (unintelligible) events effectively mystifies 
            these processes by placing them beyond our theoretical grasp. (For a 
            far more elaborated version of this same reductive abstraction see 
            Phillips 1993.) 
            But it also - and this I believe is the point of the exercise - 
            protects the idea of a self-directed consciousness by positing 
            instability as its only alternative and thereby eliminating the 
            possibility of a relatively stable, rational consciousness 
            determined by unconscious necessity. 
            The real drawback of the current wave of pseudo-synthesizing of 
            Freudian theory is that it contributes to the foreclosing of 
            important questions of history and culture. The comparative study of 
            the child's emotional struggle with the social world has, for 
            example, increased our understanding of the highly variable capacity 
            of individuals for creativity and has led to a number of penetrating 
            descriptions of the relation between creativity and the process of 
            unconscious formation (see, for example, Milner 1987.) The value of 
            this body of knowledge is its potential to allow for the progressive 
            shift from seeing the ethnographic subject as a passive conduit of 
            inherited cultural consciousness to seeing him/her as an independent 
            and imaginative person, capable of the creative reworking of 
            inherited consciousness without resorting to the illusion of 
            intentionality (an illusion which is in serious danger of becoming 
            permanently incorporated into the 'experience' of the ethnographic 
            subject.) 
            Whether or not one agrees with this particular perspective, the 
            issue Spencer's article raises is the state of an intellectual 
            culture willing to take seriously such a fundamental misreading of 
            one of this century's most influential thinkers. 
            ALEXANDRA OUTOUSSOFF London School of Economics & Political Science 
            Freud, S. 1963. Leonardo. Harmondsworth; Penguin. 
            Milner, M. 1987. The suppressed madness of sane men. London, New 
            York: Routledge. 
            Phillips, A. 1993, Contingency for beginners. Raritan 13, 54-72, 
            Ricoeur, P. 1970. Freud and philosophy: an essay on interpretation 
            (trans.) D. Savage. New Haven, London: Yale Univ. Press. 
            Rorty, R. 1989. Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Univ. 
            Press. 
            In an excellent article a few years ago Alexandra Ouroussoff(1993) 
            rightly castigated anthropologists for confusing the pieties of 
            liberal political philosophy with the real idioms and actions of 
            'modem' people living in the 'West'. Using her own ethnography from 
            a study of a major transnational corporation in Britain she 
            addressed the question of the circumstances in which people 'define 
            themselves as individuals': 'how precisely the lines of choice and 
            constraint are drawn in a social context where people imagine 
            themselves to be determining agents' (Ouroussoff 1993: 287). In my 
            article I posed the question: 'in what contexts ... do 
            "individualistic" ideas of personhood predominate and in what 
            contexts are they downplayed or denied? When is the self most easily 
            viewed as stable and enduring, and when is it better understood as a 
            temporary product of an idiosyncratic history?' (1997: 694). All 
            would seem set, then, for an interesting intellectual conversation, 
            based on our provisional answers to these questions: in Ouroussoff's 
            case, managers imagine themselves to be agents, workers are more 
            candid about the constraints of structure; in my case from Sri 
            Lanka, people normally talk as if they possess stable selves, but 
            appeal to much more decentred, evanescent notions of subjectivity in 
            moments of intense affliction. 
            Already it is clear that our projects at once overlap (in the desire 
            to problematize 'the concept of the person' through an ethnography 
            of 'person-talk'), but also differ. Ouroussoff is concerned to 
            expose the 'illusion of intentionality' and the impossible dichotomy 
            between freedom and constraint on which, she says, the Western myth 
            of the Western individual is based. I was surprised to learn that 
            'protecting this illusion does appear to be the principal task of 
            Spencer's article', as I had thought that my aims were a little 
            different. I was struck by the apparent formal similarities between 
            Rorty's reading of Freud and the accounts I had read of the Buddhist 
            doctrine of anatta or denial of the self. At this level of 
            abstraction - and explicitly avoiding all appeal to what Freud (or 
            the Buddha) 'really' meant - I found I could make some sense of my 
            own ethnographic data from a case of spirit possession in Sri Lanka 
            and also begin to make more sense of the strengths and weaknesses of 
            a book that has haunted me from the time I first read it in 1981, 
            Obeyesekere's (1981) Medusa's hair. In all this I had very little to 
            say about agency and intention: in the Abstract I refer to spirit 
            possession as an 'idiom of displaced agency', and later in the 
            article I refer to the relationship between passivity and 
            authenticity in local understandings of possession - 'any suggestion 
            of agency or authenticity on her part would render the whole 
            diagnosis suspect' (1997: 704). That is all I say on these topics. 
            There is a simple reason for this reticence. Buddhist teaching on 
            the self at once denies the reality of the self as a 'permanent, 
            everlasting and unchanging entity' (Rahula 1967: 51), yet insists on 
            the importance of 'intention' or 'volition' (cetana) as the motive 
            force in its ethicized doctrine of karma (cf. Collins 1982: 201; 
            Gombrich 1971: 244-68). The karmic force of an action depends not on 
            the outcome of the act, but on the intention of the actor, while 
            intention itself can never occur in a vacuum but is always 
            'conditioned' by its own karmic precursors. In other words, the 
            doctrinal teaching on the person links together apparently familiar 
            (or at least translatable) notions which might correspond to words 
            like 'self' or 'person', 'intention' or 'agency', but does so in a 
            quite different configuration from the one described by Ouroussoff: 
            the self is an illusion, but intention is real. What makes the self 
            real or illusory, in this view, is not especially an issue of 
            intention or agency; it is rather an issue of stability or 
            permanence. This question of stability or permanence was at the 
            heart of my article and Rorty's reading of Freud alerted me to a 
            possible parallel on this dimension. In particular, it allowed me to 
            isolate one implication of Freud's work - what Rorty (1989: 30) 
            calls his 'de-divinization' of the self - without involving my 
            argument in the whole elaborate superstructure of Freudian 
            metapsychology. This seemed ambitious enough for one article. 
            Much of the confusion is a result of the different emphases in 
            Ouroussoff's use of 'contingent' (causeless, non-necessary) and mine 
            (changing, non-stable, it could be otherwise). My argument should be 
            clear enough in the following passage: 
            The Buddhist position shares a number of features with the reading 
            of Freud put forward by Ricoeur and Rorty. Both are based on the 
            idea of a pervasive causality, although the law of cause and effect 
            in Buddhism (karma) is moral - good begets good and bad begets bad - 
            whereas Freud's is disturbingly amoral. Both are based on some idea 
            which we can gloss as 'desire' ... as a kind of final cause in the 
            whole system. And both explicitly undermine our reassuring 
            assumptions about our selves as stable, enduring essences, replacing 
            them with histories of infinite potential complexity (1997: 696). 
            Here, as elsewhere in my article, my use of the word 'history' 
            should indicate my interest in Ouroussoff's 'important questions'. 
            And, if one is interested in the idea of creativity without 
            intentionality which she raises in the penultimate paragraph of her 
            letter, I would refer her again to Obeyesekere's exemplary analysis 
            of just these issues in Medusa's hair. 
            Rereading Ouroussoff's comments, I have a growing sense that I have 
            stumbled into someone else's argument. Ouroussoff's real beef would 
            seem to be with Rorty (although a careful reading of his original 
            words would reveal more agreement with Ouroussoff than she 
            acknowledges), or more likely Phillips. I wish her well in these 
            controversies, even as I would beg to be excused from my temporary 
            role as surrogate victim, even for such luminaries as these. (Oddly 
            enough, I disagree with them too.) What I admired in Ouroussoff's 
            article on the illusions of the liberal tradition was the creative 
            interplay between broad intellectual history and insightful 
            ethnographic data. Her larger project is a serious and important 
            one. As there are enough people out there who really do hold the 
            views she is attacking - a small but increasingly insistent outbreak 
            of anthropological neoliberalism has recently been spotted to the 
            north of my office - it hardly seems necessary to impute them to 
            someone who doesn't. 
            JONATHAN SPENCER University of Edinburgh 
            Collins, S. 1982. Selfless persons: imager and thought in Theravada 
            Buddhism. Cambridge: Univ. Press. 
            Gombrich, R. 1971. Precept and practice: traditional Buddhism in the 
            rural highlands of Ceylon. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 
            Obeyesekere, G. 1981. Medusa's hair: an essay on personal symbols 
            and religious experience. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press. 
            Ouroussoff, A. 1993. Illusions of rationality: false premisses of 
            the liberal tradition. Man (N.S.) 28, 281-98. 
            Rahula, W. 1967. What the Buddha taught (2nd edn). London: Gordon 
            Fraser. 
            Rorty, R. 1989. Contingency. irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Univ. 
            Press.