Individual Buddhists. (individual growth and the Buddhist
doctrine of 'anatta' or transcendence of ego-attachment)
Michael McGhee
Religious Studies
Vol.29 No.4
Dec 1993
pp.443-452
            
COPYRIGHT Cambridge University Press 1993

            I 
            There is a short sectioa of Peter Harvey's recent book oa 
            Buddhism(1) in which he offers a thumbnail sketch of Buddhist groups 
            in the United Kingdom. Among the groups he describes is the Friends 
            of the Westera Buddhist Order, and I declare an interest, as one of 
            its members. I have no particular quarrel with the descriptioa FWBO 
            activities, but there is a sting in the tail, which is, I think, a 
            point of some conceptual interest, which others have also focused 
            oa.(2) 
            The sting is brief and cautious, perhaps too briefly and cautiously 
            inserted to constitute a clear criticism, though sufficient to 
            intimate the possibility of one, aad the tone is mildly satirical. 
            But Harvey does say enough to suggest that there is a problem, a 
            prima facie difficulty, that needs to be addressed. The difficulty, 
            in brief, is how a Buddhist Order may be supposed to reconcile an 
            emphasis on the ~individual', indeed on the growth or evea ~Higher 
            Evolutioa'(3) of the ~individual' with the (presumably ~essential') 
            Buddhist doctrine of anatta. Harvey puts it as follows: 
            In its teachings, (the FWBO) emphasises the ~Higher Evolutioa' of 
            the ~individual', such that its ideal seems to be a kind of heroic, 
            muscular, romantic superhumanism, which is influenced by some of the 
            ideas of the philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche. It thus seems to 
            neglect that aspect of the Buddhist path which ultimately aims at 
            the transcending of I-ness (sic) aad ego-attachment (p.318; my 
            italics). 
            In other words, if I may concentrate on the conceptual aspect of 
            this unfriendly appraisal, if Buddhism seeks to deny the existence 
            of the Self, at least as a permanent and substantial entity, aad if 
            it insists on the overcoming of what Harvey here calls 
            ego-attachment, how can an insistence on an individual's growth or 
            ~higher evolutioa' be reconciled with that positioa, how, indeed, 
            can it be considered a means of giving expressioa to Buddhism at 
            all, since it ~seems' to point in absolutely the wrong directioa? 
            Thus the sting. Although in this connectioa Harvey refers in his 
            bibliography only to an introductory book(4) by Dharmacari Subhuti 
            (Alex Kennedy), I should make it clear that the latter draws quite 
            explicitly on the formidable output of Sangharakshita,(5) so that if 
            we are talking about an emphasis in the FWBO on the growth aad 
            ~higher evolutioa' of the individual, we are talking about an 
            emphasis made by its founder, to whom Harvey scarcely refers. 
            Although not everyone may fiad the metaphor of a ~higher evolutioa' 
            satisfactory or immediately compelling, Sangharakshita himself makes 
            it clear that what he refers to is straightforward enough, from a 
            Buddhist point of view: to talk about the higher evolutioa of the 
            individual is intended as a means of referring to the progressive 
            stages of the path towards Buddhahood. Aad it is strange that Harvey 
            should present the emphasis on the evolutioa of the individual 
            without acknowledging that connectioa. 
            If we may leave oa one side the issue of muscular Buddhism (they 
            were young in those days) aad the slightly puzzling reference to 
            Nietzsche's Uehermensch, Harvey's suggestioa seems to be that the 
            point aad proveaance of Sangharakshita's use of the term 
            ~individual' is to be traced to the heroic individualism that one 
            fiads passim in the writings of Nietzsche, evea though the use of 
            the term is not particularly associated with him. In fact, it always 
            seemed to me that another main, aad obvious cultural influence came 
            via Kierkegaard, the European thinker who is most associated with 
            the notioa of ~the individual', aad with the use of the term. 
            No doubt there are points of contact betweea Kierkegaard aad 
            Nietzsche which are worth exploring, aad perhaps they are of more 
            interest than uncritical terms like ~superhumanism' may lead us to 
            think, though this latter expressioa may be intended by Harvey to 
            indicate a view about the level of appropriatioa of Nietzsche's 
            ideas by members of the FWBO. In any eveat, the appropriatioa of any 
            particular aspect of the work of a thinker hardly amounts to a 
            global endorsement of everything he or she says: and it would be 
            difficult to know what would count as such in the case of so subtle 
            and swiftly moving a philosopher as Nietzsche. But anyone who was 
            concerned with establishing the nature of the trajectory from the 
            absence to the achievement of the states of concentratioa upon which 
            knowledge aad visioa of things as they are is said in Buddhism to 
            depend may well fiad judicious and critical reference to Nietzsche's 
            diagnoses of the culturally received and socially reinforced forms 
            aad consequences of interaal divisioa aad emasculated relationship a 
            ~skilful means'. 
            II 
            But let us see whether the idea of the individual, at least as found 
            in Kierkegaard, aad in some of its aspects, is or is not difficult 
            to reconcile with the doctrine of anatta or the transcending of 
            ~I-ness' aad ego-attachment. 
            Are there any points of coincidence, or points at which it is 
            possible for the one traditioa to illuminate the other? Or does talk 
            of the ~Higher Evolutioa' or growth or development of the individual 
            seem after all aad irredeemably ~to neglect that aspect of the 
            Buddhist path which ultimately aims at the transcending of I-ness 
            aad ego-attachment'? 
            I shall attempt to reflect philosophically on what Kierkegaard says, 
            aad will stray in the directioa of a discussioa of the nature of 
            persoahood and self-consciousness, in ways which I think are not 
            wholly foreign to his concerns. However, my remarks in this area 
            will be relatively rudimentary, and I shall not approach head-on the 
            conceptual structures of Buddhist notioas of anatta. 
            One obvious connectioa with the Buddhist doctrine of ~not-self' 
            comes in the way in which Kierkegaard conceives the ~subjective 
            thinker' as ~essentially interested in his own thinking, existing as 
            he does in his thought'. I take the expressioa, ~existing as he does 
            in his thought', to be an attempt to capture the idea that the 
            energies of the human persoa are constructed round those forms of 
            thought which motivate them to actioa, so that they exist and move 
            within horizoas of thought which focus their energies and determine 
            their reasoas for actioa. I make the connectioa with actioa in an 
            attempt to alleviate the residual Cartesianism of Kierkegaard's 
            thinking, which sits ill with his emphasis oa relationship. 
            The term ~subjective' has become hopelessly impoverished in its use 
            in recent times, so there are real difficulties in retrieving 
            Kierkegaard's thought. But despite the connotatioas that an 
            expressioa like ~subjective thinker' is now likely to have, it seems 
            to me that its sense as used by Kierkegaard is something like ~the 
            self-aware or self-conscious thinker', so long as we make clear that 
            what we are conscious of as a Kierkegaardian ~existing individual' 
            is our thinking. This is an important qualificatioa, since it 
            implies a particular form of self-consciousness. I can be aware of 
            what I am doing, for instance, or be aware of a particular desire or 
            impulse to actioa, and be aware of it in terms that reflect my 
            established way of thinking (in the light of which an impulse or 
            desire might appear acceptable or unacceptable, for example). But to 
            become aware precisely of my thinking is to gain a purchase oa its 
            totality. But this oaly makes sense if we can acknowledge, not only 
            that my established ways of thinking can change, but also that the 
            tip of the terms of that change is already available within the 
            emergent attitudes implicit in the form of self-consciousness. One 
            correcting modificatioa of the Kierkegaardian insistence on an 
            awareness of our thinking is to insist on an (attitudinal) awareness 
            of our form of life, or the general form of our relationship. 
            (Needless to say, to be self-aware or self-conscious here carries no 
            implications about awareness of a Self conceived as independent of 
            the interaal and behavioural processes that make up human 
            experience: the sort of Self that Hume very properly professed 
            himself unable to fiad. On the contrary, to be self-aware in this 
            context is to be aware of precisely those processes. What I started 
            to spell out, aad it is of central importance in understanding the 
            anatta doctrine, is that such self-awareness is attitudinal, or 
            ~from a point of view': in being aware of what we are doing, for 
            example, we are sometimes ~uneasily' or ~critically' aware. This 
            unease may derive from our established modes of thoughts, or, on the 
            other hand, it may transcend them.) 
            In the Concluding Unscientific Postscript(6) Kierkegaard establishes 
            a connectioa betweea the idea of ~the subjective thinker' and that 
            of ~the existing individual' thus: 
            While objective thought is indifferent to the thinking subject and 
            his existence, the subjective thinker is as an existing individual 
            essentially interested in his own thinking, existing as he does in 
            his thought (p. 67). 
            In a note about this passage, after going on to discuss very 
            suggestively the nature of the communicatioa that is appropriate to 
            these different modes of thought, objective and subjective, 
            Kierkegaard twice makes the point that the existing individual (here 
            the ~religious individual') is in ~constant process of becoming' 
            (~inwardly' or ~in inwardness'). 
            It is clear, as we shall see in a momeat, that these two ideas, 
            ~existing in thought', and being in constant process of becoming, 
            are closely connected. Admittedly, the contexts to which Kierkegaard 
            appeals at this point are the erotic relationship aad the 
            God-relationship, aad it would be absurd to attempt to show that 
            ~really' Kierkegaard is attempting to express ~a Buddhist thought'. 
            Manifestly he is seeking to do no such thing, if we examine the 
            larger context. But a Buddhist thinker does not need to press 
            Kierkegaard's thoughts in an alien directioa in order to fiad 
            features of his thinking a helpful means of expressing ideas that 
            may in the end he alien to Kierkegaard. Furthermore, the two 
            references I have just made to different forms of communicatioa aad 
            to different forms of relationship make it quite clear that despite 
            the apparent idealist bias of his focus on thinking, aad the 
            apparent self-absorptioa of his preoccupatioa with inwardness, 
            Kierkegaard is quite emphatic that the true individual exists in 
            relationship, the form of which changes with, because it expresses, 
            changes in the form of inwardness.(7) 
            The subjective thinker, the existing individual, who is essentially 
            interested in his own thinking, existing as he does in his thought, 
            is contrasted with someone who, in a religious or ethical context, 
            merely thinks ~in an objective manner' (which is, remember, 
            ~indifferent to the thinking subject and his existence'). The 
            subjective thinker is contrasted with someone, that is to say, in 
            whom there does not occur what is essential to religious thinking, 
            namely the subjective appropriatioa in inwardness of that which is 
            thought, a process in which the individual is transformed pari passu 
            with the development of his thought. Indeed, the trajectory of the 
            ~constant process of becoming' to which Kierkegaard refers may be 
            said to be traceable along the path of what constitutes the 
            appropriatioa of the existing individual's thought. The point we can 
            retrieve from Kierkegaard about ~subjective thinking' is that it is 
            an activity of thought which, so far from being exteraal to the 
            formatioa of the individual thus engaged, is just what forms him or 
            her as a persoa. 
            If one remains merely an objective thinker, on the other hand, so 
            that one ~knows' the various religious and spiritual truths oaly 
            ~objectively', aad not otherwise, as though they had no impact oa 
            one's ~inwardness', thea one has precisely failed to understand 
            them. Remaining undisturbed by a disturbing thought, to put it 
            crudely, one shows one's incompreheasioa. One knows that one is 
            mortal in the way that one knows other pieces of informatioa that do 
            not (particularly) affect us. If it is true that certain thoughts 
            affect us aad make a difference, and one remains unaffected and no 
            difference is made, then one reasoa for this may be that we have not 
            ~subjectively appropriated' the relevant thoughts at all. If you 
            really understood that you were mortal, the claim goes, then you 
            would be changed. Such claims are presumably made on the basis of an 
            accumulated experience of determinate changes in determinate 
            circumstances. That such changes occur is the ground of 
            Kierkegaard's enterprise, aad is the conditioa of his sensitivity to 
            the difficulties of communicatioa betweea persoas established at 
            different points along the line of transformatioa, a line of 
            transformatioa which (if it exists, and we can hardly be neutral 
            here) determines for us the criteria for what persoas are in the 
            first place. 
            No doubt Kierkegaard is thinking in schematic terms aad it would be 
            pointless to press him too hard. What seems to make one an 
            ~objective thinker' in relation to classes of thought the proper 
            understanding of which involves an ~inward' dimensioa is precisely 
            the failure to be aware of this dimensioa, so that one behaves as 
            though there were no grammatical difference (to use a 
            Wittgensteinian expressioa) betweea, say, ~spiritual truths' aad 
            ordinary matters of fact of the kind that do not (much) impinge upoa 
            us. But it is this absence of inwardness that is the real issue. It 
            is what is ~really' wrong with the ~objective thinker'. If one 
            remains a ~merely' objective thinker then one fails to be ~an 
            existing individual', that is to say, one fails to be ~essentially 
            interested' in one's own thinking. One's attention may be focused in 
            directioas aad forms of relationship determined by one's actual, 
            one's established, thoughts and desires, but there is no movement of 
            self-consciousness of a kind sufficient to allow one to realise, for 
            instance, that one ~exists in (one's) thought', or to realise, 
            perhaps, the determinants of one's thoughts and desires, or their 
            connectioa with the culturally received aad reinforced disharmonies 
            and repressioas. Without that movement of self-consciousness, one 
            remains, unawares, in the grip of ego-formatioas aad their forms of 
            expressioa and relationship that, in traditioaal Buddhist terms, are 
            limited by craving, aversioa and ignorance, and which one may very 
            well think is ~one's very self' (though that is a delusioa which 
            depends on some degree of self-awareness). It is not that the 
            ~objective thinker' does not ~reflect' upoa his or her life or has 
            no self-awareness. The terms in which he or she reflects upoa his or 
            her life simply reduplicate the established way of thinking; that is 
            what he or she fails to reflect upoa, the totality of the 
            established way of thinking itself. Aad this is the essential point: 
            if he or she did reflect upoa his or her established way of thinking 
            it would, as I have said, have to be ~in terms', though, of course, 
            in other terms than those available in the established way of 
            thinking; it would have to be from a point of view, which we should 
            have to understand as an emergent point of view, so that the momeat 
            of (attitudinal) self-consciousness of the totality of one's way of 
            thinking is also a momeat of revelation. It is also the momeat at 
            which one starts to become what an individual persoa is. The first 
            movement of the ~existing individual' is to become aware of, thence 
            to pursue, emergent forms of inwardness, to enter thus a determinate 
            process of becoming, a process by which one is constituted as a 
            persoa. 
            One way of making sense of what Kierkegaard is trying to say about 
            ~inwardness' and ~subjective appropriatioa' is to think of certain 
            beliefs or thoughts or facts as having, under relevant conditioas, a 
            known motivatioaal efficacy, and as having this precisely because 
            such beliefs or thoughts or facts represent the intentioaal objects 
            of an emergent sensibility or form of inwardness. To think such 
            thoughts ~subjectively' is to allow their content to affect one's 
            inwardness, aad is to have regard to the form of their impact. The 
            criteria of identity for the thought include the form of that 
            inwardness. To put it in Wittgensteinian terms, the form of one's 
            inwardness represents the grammar of one's ~thought' in the sense 
            that one's inwardness is constituted by the constellatioa of 
            conceptually related other thoughts, images, impulses, etc. which 
            give one's ~thought' its specific identity within a set of relations 
            as the thought that it is. When such a ~thought' is thought ~in an 
            objective manner', on the other hand, there is no such hinterland. 
            This is not to say that there is no hinterland in the objective 
            thinker: it will simply not be that which belongs to the grammar of 
            the unappropriated thought. 
            If the existing individual is essentially interested in his or her 
            own thinking, existing as he or she does in his or her thoughts, 
            then presumably he or she has begun to realise that such a relation 
            exists, and this is a feature of his or her becoming what he or she 
            is, his or her emergence as an individual (persoa) : his or her 
            growth as an individual will then be a functioa of the transforming 
            thoughts that he or she appropriates, and which manifest themselves 
            in changed forms of relationship (Regine). Aa ~existing individual' 
            is a persoa who has started to become what a persoa is. This may 
            sound paradoxical. If we were to discover that persoas were 
            constituted in a series of determinate transformatioas, which were 
            dependent upoa conditioas, including, say, the access of 
            self-awareness, then we should be able to make sense of the idea of 
            a persoa becoming what a persoa is, since we should then conceive 
            persoahood as an essentially developmental notioa: it could be true 
            of a persoa that he or she had yet to become what a persoa is. So 
            our conceptioa of ~what a persoa is' may be determined by the 
            experience of some at least of the trajectories traced within the 
            religious and spiritual traditioas, in ways no doubt contested 
            betweea those traditioas, which is to say that ~what a persoa is' is 
            also a matter of contest.(8)but whatever differences there may be 
            betweea them, more than one spiritual traditioa shares the idea that 
            the ~constant process of becoming' takes a determinate and to some 
            extent determinable directioa, manifested, again, in demeanour and 
            relationship, which must surely be the real form of this becoming, 
            so that it makes good sense to say that persoas need to become what 
            persoas are. Our sense of ~what persoas are' is partly determined by 
            the extent of our appropriatioa of such processes of change as have 
            been initiated and developed in the traditioa, and given 
            characteristic forms of expressioa in the language aad the spiritual 
            community, aad may be partly determined, indeed, by what remains to 
            be initiated. Kierkegaard himself talks of ~a complete 
            transformatioa of an individual's subjectivity', aad such a notioa 
            provides the perspective from which the distinctioa betweea the 
            subjective thinker aad the objective thinker becomes a possibility. 
            It provides the perspective from which the objective thinker appears 
            to remain precisely unbudging, aad the perspective from which the 
            problem of communicatioa becomes recognisably acute. He or she has 
            yet to initiate the process by which he or she becomes, precisely, 
            an individual. The conditioas for the possibility of doing so are 
            already established, to put it in Buddhist terms, in the many forms 
            of dukkha that flesh is heir to, which include, at a pre-reflective 
            level, forms of unsatisfactoriness or unease which are the first 
            intimatioa in our attitudinal self-consciousness of emergent 
            motivatioas attention to or disregard of which precipitates the 
            directioas of possible change. 
            III 
            Evea in the terms offered by Kierkegaard, we are clearly not too far 
            removed from certain aspects of the anatta doctrine, even though he 
            is precisely attempting to represent the state of the ~true 
            individual', an emphasis on the growth or development or even 
            ~Higher Evolutioa' of whom, it will be remembered, is taken by 
            Harvey to seem to neglect that aspect of the Buddhist path whose 
            ultimate aim is the transcending of I-ness aad ego-attachment. 
            After all, if we were to seek to represent that aim in terms related 
            to what we have just discussed, we should presumably want to say 
            that the unregenerate persoa who remains an ~objective thinker' is 
            constituted by a set of thoughts, an ego-formatioa, if you like, 
            with which he or she identifies, and to which, in consequence, he or 
            she is attached, in such a way that his or her state of mind, 
            mind-set or citta, manifests ego-attachment aad the 
            non-transcendence of ~I-ness'. The so-called subjective thinker on 
            the other hand is at least in a position to know better because, to 
            the extent that he or she has realised that he or she is in constant 
            process of becoming, he or she has also realised, at the very least, 
            that he or she has no good reason to remain attached to some 
            specific ego-formatioa. We do not need to represent Kierkegaard as 
            being ready to offer such as characterisatioa of the mental state of 
            his objective thinker, or of the directioa of his or her ~becoming', 
            but he has certainly provided us with a vocabulary in which we caa, 
            a vocabulary, moreover, which reveals his insight into our 
            constitutioa in thought-processes, aad his insight that one's 
            emergence as an individual, a persoa ia the process of becoming what 
            a persoa is, begins in the critical appropriatioa of culturally or 
            interpersoaally received spiritual or religious truths. Again, his 
            own distinctioa betweea subjective aad objective thought is an 
            ethical one, evea if he has a different conceptioa of ethics. The 
            point, to repeat it, is not to say that Kierkegaard is really a 
            Buddhist, but to say that there is an enabling coincidence of 
            thinking which allows expressioa, in a western context, of a 
            Buddhist thought. 
            Now the many-sided Buddhist doctrine of anatta is difficult to make 
            sense of even though it may be relatively easy to state. There are 
            difficulties, for instance, about the derivatioa of the criteria of 
            ~Selfhood' (in terms of permanence aad substantiality, etc.) by 
            reference to which particular ~things', including the human persoa, 
            are judged to be ~not-self'. This is not the place for a proper 
            discussioa of how we should approach or understand such a notioa. 
            What I shall do, though, is refer to Harvey's own statement of the 
            doctrine, to see how far, thus stated, it may be connected with talk 
            of the growth of the individual: 
            the not-self teaching does not deny that there is continuity of 
            character in life, and to some extent from life to life. But 
            persistent character traits are merely due to the repeated 
            occurrence of certain cittas or ~mind-sets'. The citta as a whole is 
            sometimes talked of as an (empirical) ~self'... but while such 
            character traits may be long-lasting, they caa and do change, and 
            are thus impermanent, aad so ~not-self', insubstantial. A ~persoa' 
            is a collectioa of rapidly changing and interacting mental and 
            physical processes, with character patterns re-occurring over some 
            time. Only partial control caa be exercised over these processes; so 
            they often change in undesired ways, leading to suffering. 
            Impermanent, they caanot be a permanent self Suffering, they caanot 
            be aa autonomous true ~I', which would contain nothing that was out 
            of harmony with itself (op. Cit. P. 52, my italics). 
            The coda reflects the difficulties I have just referred to about the 
            criteria for Selfhood, but the immediately relevant passage is the 
            one that says that a ~persoa' is to be understood as a collectioa of 
            rapidly changing and interacting mental and physical processes, 
            since this seems readily intelligible ia terms of the notioa of the 
            individual, as conceived by Kierkegaard. That is to say, such a 
            thinker recognises that he is constituted by his thought. In a 
            constant process of becoming, the general directioa of that change 
            is dependent upoa conditioas, conditioas which include attention and 
            active thinking of a kind I have just characterised, including the 
            cultivatioa, development or growth of the attitudes implicit in the 
            forms of self-consciousness we have been discussing. It is clear 
            that for Kierkegaard there is an ethical dimensioa to this process 
            of becoming, just as in Buddhism there is an ethical dimensioa to 
            the possible directioas, dependent upoa conditioas, of the rapidly 
            changing mental processes that Harvey refers to. What is castigated 
            by Kierkegaard is the failure to appropriate religious and ethical 
            truths. An unregenerate ~mind-set', to use Harvey's phrase, remains 
            intact, untouched, by precisely what touches the psyche, while the 
            subjective thinker is transformed and reconstituted by the impact of 
            these same ~thoughts'. 
            The nature of persoaal transformatioa aad the growth of the 
            individual exemplifies a particular applicatioa, then, of 
            ~conditioaed co-productioa', aad so, by the criteria according to 
            which anything is judged to be ~not-self', the individual human 
            being is to that extent ~anatta' or, to put it in other terms, 
            ~empty of inherent existence'. The transformatioas of the 
            individual, by which he or she becomes what he or she is perceived 
            in the spiritual tradition to be, are dependent upoa conditioas 
            which include the initial sense of dukkha, attention to which 
            initiates change. 
            Kierkegaard was much exercised by the problem of becoming what oae 
            is, by the problem, that is to say, of starting the process of 
            thought within whose transformatioas one is constituted. To start to 
            realise that one's mind-set is dependent upoa conditioas, and to 
            realise that, for more than one reasoa, that mind-set is dukkha, is 
            already to recognise, to some extent, that one is not a permanent 
            and fixed ego: such recognitioa, of course, must confront the 
            resistances associated with attachment to particular mind-sets as 
            though they were one's very self -- which is not to assert (or deny) 
            that one's very self is to be found elsewhere. Harvey underlines 
            Buddhist pragmatism here very well. One could say that our concept 
            of selfhood is radically contaminated by the mind-set of ~this is 
            mine', ~I am this', to such an extent, indeed, that talk of an 
            Upanishadic self (truth-value, the real state of things, quite 
            aside), is hound to be misunderstood, aad the search for it become 
            no more than a reinforcement of what Harvey calls ego-attachment. 
            If we see the human persoa as essentially anatta in the sense 
            discussed, i.e. as essentially in process, though in determinate 
            directioas discovered and articulated in the traditioa, we caa 
            perhaps begin to see that an attention to the growth, development, 
            evolutioa of the individual is so far from neglecting the Buddhist 
            emphasis on the transcending of ~I-ness' aad ego-attachment, that it 
            is actually a conditioa of its possibility! 
            It is hard to see how Harvey is not acknowledging as much when he 
            says, for instance: 
            Much Buddhist practice is concerned with the purificatioa, 
            development and integratioa of the factors of persoaality, through 
            the cultivatioa of virtue aad meditatioa. In time, however, the 
            five-fold aaalysis is used to enable a meditator to gradually 
            transcend the naive perceptioa -- with respect to ~himself' or 
            ~another' -- of a unitary ~persoa' or ~self'. In place of this there 
            is set up the contemplatioa of a persoa as a cluster of changing 
            mental and physical processes, or dhamma's, thus undermining 
            grasping and attachment, which are key causes of suffering (op. cit. 
            P. 50). 
            The essential or determining act of the individual is the movement 
            of self-conciousness in which one becomes aware of oneself as 
            constituted in change aad as constituted in one's thought, where the 
            line of one's becoming is to be located in the line of one's 
            ~thought'. The idea of the purificatioa, development and harmonious 
            integratioa of the factors of persoaality, as Harvey expresses it, 
            is entirely compatible with such an idea of the ~individual', 
            especially since it describes a process which terminates in a clear 
            recognitioa of the real nature of things, a truth which, in 
            Kierkegaardiaa terms, caa only be subjectively appropriated, aad, in 
            Buddhist terms, is only so appropriated by a highly evolved, because 
            highly concentrated, individual. The process of purificatioa, etc. 
            that Harvey very properly describes, is a process of transformatioa, 
            from one state of the persoa to another. The gibe about the FWBO and 
            its emphasis on the ~individual' must surely rely oa a vulgar 
            conceptioa of that term, assimilating it, perhaps, to some kind of 
            cultivatioa of a preferred self-image, or similar narcissism, as 
            though the growth of the individual was not partly constituted at 
            least by the development of an ethical sensibility made manifest in 
            changes in relationship, 
            Ia conclusioa, it might be worth attempting to articulate what I 
            have said about self-consciousness in terms of the khandhas. Part of 
            the philosophical interest of the five khandha doctrine construed as 
            an aaalysis of the general form of human experience, is that it 
            already includes an account of what Kierkegaard is struggling for in 
            his talk of inwardness aad appropriatioa. It precisely locates 
            ~thought' in the world of form (rupa) (its intentional object) aad 
            makes essential reference to feeling (vedaaa) aad motivatioa 
            (sankhara) as well as discriminatioa (sanaa) aad the degrees of 
            self-consciousness (vinaaaa) which are correlated with their 
            development: one must, on Kierkegaard's terms, ~be essentially 
            interested' in one's own thinking, a process of attention which 
            itself begins to alter the general frame of what is there to be 
            conscious of, since such attention allows it to emerge. Ia other 
            words, progressive changes of an ethical kind within the sankharas 
            are made possible by the feature of self-consciousness I have 
            already referred to. Self-consciousness is already attitudinal, aad 
            either merely reduplicates the general form of one's actually 
            motivating thought, or, by contrast, provides a purchase upoa it, in 
            the form of nascent and emergent forms of motivatioa. So higher 
            sankharas are already present in the forms of reflectioa of the 
            existing individual: or at least, their intimatioas in the forms of 
            reflectioa, duly attended to, are a conditioa of their development, 
            a development which will have repercussioas for the scope and focus 
            of sanaa. (1) Peter Harvey, An Introductioa to Buddhism (Cambridge 
            University Press, 1990). (2) See P. A. Mellor, ~Protestant 
            Buddhism?' Religioa, xxi (1991), 82. (3) An expressioa used by the 
            founder of the Western Buddhist Order, Sangharakshita. (4) 
            Dharmacari Subhuti (Alex Kennedy), Buddhism for Today (Glasgow, 
            1988). (5) For a recent account of the idea of a ~higher evolutioa' 
            aad a response to P. A. Mellor's assess of FWBO beliefs and 
            attitudes, see Sangharakshita, The FWBO and ~Protestant Buddhism' 
            (Windhorse Publicatioas, 1992). (6) Trans. David F. Swensoa aad 
            Walter Lowrie (Princetoa, 1968). (7) Cf. what Kierkegaard says about 
            the ~loving maiden' in the note referred to above. (8) See Rowan 
            Williams' discussioa in his "Know Thyself": What kind of an 
            Injunctioa?'in McGhee ed.), Philosophy, Religioa aad the Spiritual 
            Life (Cambridge, 1992).