Religious nationalism and democratic polity: the Indian case

T.K. Oommen

Sociology of Religion
Vol.55 No.4 (Winter 1994)
pp.455-472

COPYRIGHT Association for the Sociology of Religion 1994


            In this article I propose to argue that religious nationalism and 
            democratic polity cannot co-exist harmoniously, particularly in a 
            society characterized by religious diversity. Yet, some religious 
            collectivities advance the claim that they are "nations." The claim 
            to nationality/nationhood can succeed only if the religions under 
            reference press into service a domain assumption, an ideological 
            tenet and two strategies, all of which are logically linked. The 
            domain assumption is that there is a conterminality between religion 
            and territory; the ideological tenet is homogenization of the 
            society by imposing the life-style associated with the religious 
            collectivity asserting or aspiring to nationhood -- that is, 
            establishing hegemony over the dominated religious collectivities. 
            The strategies pursued to achieve the goal are communalization and 
            relativization, which are logical corollaries of territorialization 
            and homogenization, respectively -- all of which are antithetical to 
            the ethos of democracy. My concern in this article is with the 
            articulations of religious nationalisms in India. I shall desist 
            from the temptation of tracing the trajectories of these religious 
            nationalisms -- Hindu, Muslim, and Sikh -- because they are well 
            known and well documented. Instead, I will endeavor to show that the 
            assumptions, ideologies and strategies invoked by these religious 
            communities to buttress their claims are not sustainable. It may be 
            noted here in passing that the other varieties of nationalisms in 
            India based on language and tribe are qualitatively different 
            because they meet the critical minimum conditions for nation 
            formation. That is, they are territorially anchored speech 
            communities. SOME CONCEPTUAL CLARIFICATIONS It is necessary to 
            indicate at this juncture that there are only two basic conditions 
            for the formation of nations (Oommen 1994): The first condition is a 
            territory on which the inhabitants have a moral claim either because 
            it is their original homeland or because they come to identify with 
            it as their homeland as migrants, colonizers or even conquerors (cf. 
            Hertz 1945:145-51). Generally one is apt to reject the claims made 
            by conquerors and colonizers as immoral or illegal if this happened 
            in the recent past. But one should not fall victim to the prevailing 
            instant contemporization of social reality. There are numerous 
            instances in history when in a short span of time -- say, a few 
            hundred years or so -- colonizing populations have completely 
            identified themselves with the territory into which they moved as 
            their homeland. By contrast, even after several centuries of 
            expatriate existence, persecuted peoples have returned to their 
            homeland with alacrity. Therefore the point at issue is not the 
            length of time involved as such, though a critical minimum period is 
            often necessary for nativization, but the attitude of the colonizing 
            people to the new territory and the legitimacy they acquire. If a 
            people do not identify with the land into which they migrate, they 
            remain an ethnie. The second condition for the formation of a nation 
            is a common instrument of communication, a language. This language 
            need not be a highly developed one but good enough to transact the 
            business of everyday life such as conducting administration, 
            processing disputes, imparting elementary education, undertaking 
            worship, expressing affection and love. Admittedly, a nation that 
            wants to "modernize" itself should either develop its own language 
            or adopt another developed language to absorb and communicate modern 
            knowledge. This, however, does not mean that the adopted language 
            should necessarily displace the "national" one. It is important to 
            note here that these two objective conditions need not always lead 
            to the crystallization of nationalism, the subjective consciousness 
            a people develops about their common history, experience, and 
            destiny. That is, even as a concrete nation is a prerequisite for 
            the emergence of nationalism, it is not a sufficient condition. 
            Often it is a sense of deprivation, objective or subjective, that 
            provided the prerequisite for the emergence of nationalism. Further, 
            there is no inherent tendency for a nation to establish its own 
            state, although this is taken to be axiomatic based on the limited 
            European experience (Weber 1948). A multinational state is not only 
            a viable project under certain conditions but often an 
            imperative.(1) However, there are several instances in history when 
            a "nation" is sought to be established invoking religion, ignoring 
            the crucial importance of common language and contiguous territory. 
            These religious nationalisms are unsustainable in the long run, as 
            exemplified by the division of Pakistan in 1971. It follows that a 
            multinational state is plurilingual, and each of the nations 
            encapsulated within it would have its own specific territory and 
            language. That is, the constituting elements of a multinational 
            state are nations without states. The notion of nation-state implies 
            a situation of controlled and restricted spatial mobility beyond 
            state boundaries. Nations today are characterized by frayed edges 
            and loose textures, and they are constantly exposed to alien 
            influences through communication and migration. This calls for a 
            link language and not necessarily a "national" language in the case 
            of multinational states, as there would be several national 
            languages in such a state. Only those who are in constant 
            interaction with people, agencies and organizations located outside 
            their nations need to know the link language, the common instrument 
            of communication. To insist on a lingua franca for the whole 
            population of a multinational state is unnecessary and irrational, 
            usually the starting point for the emergence of nationalism within 
            state societies (cf. Gellner 1983). TERRITORIALIZATION By 
            territorialization I am referring to a tendency on the part of a 
            religious collectivity to claim that a specific territory is its 
            exclusive homeland. First, it may be noted that such a claim is 
            logically untenable in the case of proselytizing religions such as 
            Buddhism, Christianity, and Islam. (This is not to deny that these 
            religions have sacred sites and cities, even city states.) Through 
            conquest and colonialism these religious collectivities have been 
            dispersed to vast territories far beyond the lands of their origin. 
            The project of Christianizing the world and the notion of universal 
            Islam rebel against territorialization. In fact, the main anchorages 
            of proselytizing religions are in alien lands. Thus while there are 
            several Buddhist majority nations in the world, those who profess 
            Buddhism constitute a mere 0.70 percent of the population in India. 
            The biggest two enclaves of Islam are South Asia (India, Pakistan 
            and Bangladesh) and Indonesia. Christianity was appropriated by 
            Europe and then spread to Latin America, Africa, and Asia. However, 
            the conterminality between territory and religion, though logically 
            sustainable in the case of nonproselytizing religions such as 
            Judaism and Hinduism, is not historically sustainable in these cases 
            either. As I have suggested earlier, the disjuncture between 
            territory and culture leads to the ethnification of a people, but 
            they could and usually do acquire nationhood by eventual 
            identification with the new homeland, a course open to the Jews too. 
            The argument that because of discrimination, persecution and 
            genocide, the Jews could not identify with their new homelands is 
            not applicable in all situations. For example Jews were not 
            persecuted or discriminated against in India, yet they left for 
            Israel in the wake of the Zionist movement. On the other hand, it is 
            not true that all Jews who returned to Israel were equally 
            successful in identifying with Israel as their homeland. Racial and 
            linguistic factors often came in the way to block this claim. 
            Clearly religion could not provide authentic content to nationhood 
            even in the case of Jews. Hinduism, as noted above is also a 
            nonproselytizing religion, and the notion of a Hindus Rashtra 
            (nation) is very much in vogue today.(2) But a moment's reflection 
            makes it amply clear that the concept of a Hindu nation is not 
            sustainable. The contemporary notion of Hinduism is a product of a 
            long process of encounters between dissenting sects professing 
            diverse beliefs, and with other religions, particularly Islam and 
            Christianity. While the British colonial policy did partially 
            contribute to the emergence of the new Hindu and Muslim identities 
            in communal-national terms (see Pandey 1990), Miller's conclusion 
            (1991:169) appears to be cautious and careful: By their education, 
            legislation, administration, judicial codes and procedures and even 
            by that apparently simple operation of "objective" classification, 
            the census, the British unwittingly imposed dualistic "either-or" 
            oppositions as the natural normative order of thought. In a 
            multitude of ways, Indians learned that one is either this or that; 
            that one cannot be both or neither or indifferent. The significance 
            of identity thus became a new paramount concern. . . an orthodoxy of 
            being was gradually replacing a heterodoxy of beings. It is 
            important to insist that the Hindu identity is neither entirely new 
            nor completely old; it is a conjoint product of both contemporary 
            construction and the givens of the past. The cultural symbols and 
            the values that embody them have a recognizable trajectory, some of 
            which are newly constructed to cope with the challenge posed by the 
            semitic religions. On the other hand, some of these values and 
            symbols are activization of old ones, indeed revivals. It is this 
            past-present linkage that imparts to the new identity its vibrancy 
            and vitality, on the one hand, and its ambiguity and ambivalence, on 
            the other. This is evident from the differing boundary demarcations 
            of Hinduism, which fall on a continuum. That is, there are a series 
            of Hindu identities and not just one ideal type. Let me list the 
            three most prominent ones. First, Hindus are simply the original and 
            obvious inhabitants of Hindustan, that is, India. "Hindu society 
            living in this country since times immemorial is the national . . . 
            society here. . . . The same Hindu people have built the 
            life-values, ideals and culture of this country and, therefore, 
            their nationhood is self-evident" (cited in Goyal 1979:40). Further, 
            "!w^e, Hindus, have been in undisputed and undisturbed possession of 
            this land for over eight or even ten thousand years before the land 
            was invaded by any foreign race" (Golwalkar 1939:49). Viewed thus, 
            Hindus are simply a people who occupy their homeland and share a 
            lifestyle. This all-embracing definition does not have religious 
            content, Hindus being a people of a designated land, as the Germans 
            or the Greeks are. Second, Hindus are all those who pursue religions 
            of Indian origin, including the primal vision. Thus Savarkar 
            contends: "Hinduism must necessarily mean the religion or the 
            religions that are peculiar or native to this land. . . . !I^t 
            should be applied to all the religious beliefs that the different 
            communities of the Hindu people hold" (1949:104-5). In this 
            conceptualization, the inextricable linkage between the community of 
            faith and the country of residence is taken to be the essence of the 
            Hindu nation. But such a proposition would be rejected by the 
            "non-Hindu" religions of Indian origin as antidemocratic, and some 
            have openly challenged it (e.g., Sikhs); hence the following 
            clarification: Sikhs are Hindus in the sense of our definition of 
            Hindutva and not in any religious sense whatever. Religiously they 
            are Sikhs as Jains are Jains, Lingayats are Lingayats, Vaishnavas 
            are Vaishnavas; but all of us racially and nationally and culturally 
            are a polity and a people. . . . We are Sikhs and Hindus and 
            Bharatiyas (Indians). We are all three put together and none 
            exclusively (Savarkar 1949:125). Clearly this studied ambivalence 
            and cultivated ambiguity is a political project designed to avoid 
            possible wedges and potential conflicts between religions of Indian 
            origin. Be that as it may, this definition of Hindu is both 
            inclusive (all those who profess religions of Indian origin) and 
            exclusive (all those who profess religions of "alien" origin). The 
            third conceptualization of Hindu is more restrictive and 
            substantially exclusivist. It includes (a) only twice-born Brahmins, 
            Kshatriyas and Vaishyas or, at best, also ritually clean Shudras, 
            (b) of Aryabhumi, that is, North India. It excludes the Panchamas 
            (those of the fifth order) that is, the ex-untouchables currently 
            counting a hundred million;(3) the Adivasis (the original 
            inhabitants), presently accounting for fifty million;(4) and 
            Dravidian Hindus of South India, numbering around two hundred 
            million.(5) This conceptualization questions the internality of a 
            substantial proportion of "Hindus"; they are rendered "outsiders" 
            (Oommen 1990a:43-66). Clearly, such a definition of Hindu falls 
            short of the requirements of a political project; it divides the 
            Hindus of India into different "nations." To avoid the extreme 
            exclusivist orientation of this conceptualization, neo-Hindu 
            reformers have attempted to accommodate non-Hindus through Shuddhi 
            (ritual purification). But the innovation is applicable only to (a) 
            ritually unclean untouchables; (b) the tribal communities, that is, 
            Vanvasis (forest dwellers) who claim primal vision as their 
            religion; and (c) those who have been converted into "alien" 
            religions. For the Dravidian clean caste Hindus, Shuddhi is 
            irrelevant. Thus once again one encounters the ambiguity of boundary 
            and ambivalence of attitude in defining Hindu and Hinduism. The 
            caste and linguistic factors invoked in defining Hinduism erode the 
            saliency of religion. Hindu is thus defined at least in three 
            different ways invoking different variables: territory, religion, 
            and caste or language. All of them pose problems in defining Hindu 
            as a nation or nationality, and I shall list them presently. But 
            what is common to all the three conceptualizations is that they deny 
            equality to one or another segment of the population, the very 
            antithesis of democracy. It is true that 83 percent of the Indian 
            population is classified as Hindu in the census.(6) To begin, it may 
            be noted that the claim that India is the Hindu homeland was made 
            with reference to undivided India in which the proportion of Hindus 
            was much less than that in divided India. On the other hand, 
            undivided India had the largest Muslim congregation in the world. 
            Even after partition, India remains the second largest Muslim 
            country in the world. Similarly, 80 percent of the world's 
            Zoroastrians live in India. Hindu nationalists counter this point by 
            suggesting that these people are outsiders raises the question as to 
            the time span required for the nativization of a people in a 
            country. The Zoroastrians have been in India since the eighth 
            century. The Muslims came to the Kerala coast as early as the 
            seventh century. The Syrian Christians of Kerala claim to be 
            converts since 52 A.D. At any rate, an overwhelming majority of 
            Muslims and Christians are converts from Scheduled Castes and 
            Scheduled Tribes, the original inhabitants of India. Therefore, if 
            one takes the criterion of nativity seriously, a majority of the 
            Muslims and Christians have a better claim to be Indian nationals 
            because the Aryan Hindus, who claim to be the original inhabitants, 
            came to India only some 3,500 years ago. The attitude of Hindu 
            nationalists varies enormously in regard to the different religious 
            categories, viewed in terms of their sources of presence and modes 
            of incorporation. All religions of Indian origin are considered as 
            Hinduism according to one of the conceptualizations as noted above. 
            However, this expansionist orientation in defining Hindus is 
            resented by some, the most obvious case being that of the Sikhs in 
            independent India, as they too claim to be a nation based on the 
            criterion of religion. The Hindu-Sikh conflict, then, is to be 
            viewed as the competing claims of two religious nationalisms. Be 
            that as it may, the Sikh accusation that Hindu nationalists are 
            antidemocratic is equally applicable to Sikh nationalists, as both 
            tend to be hegemonic. Generally speaking, Hindu nationalists have an 
            attitude of indifference and even tolerance toward the "migrant" 
            religions -- Jews, Zoroastrians and Baha'is -- not simply because 
            their numbers are very small and hence they do not pose any threat, 
            but also because they have not claimed any part of the Indian 
            territory as their homeland and have not indulged in 
            proselytization.(7) However, the Hindu nationalists have had an 
            uneasy relation and a hostile attitude toward Christians and 
            Muslims, although it has varied in intensity. The negative attitude 
            to Indian Christians was part of the hostility toward British 
            rulers, as both were co-religionists and hence an instant object of 
            suspicion. The persisting hostility toward Christians after the exit 
            of the British can be traced to the continuing missionary activity, 
            often geared to proselytization. This hostility is moderated by two 
            factors. First, Indian Christians never defined themselves as a 
            nationality and have not even demanded any special benefits from the 
            state on the basis of religion. (However, Christian converts from 
            the Scheduled Castes and their spokespersons do demand such benefits 
            now, as conversion has not improved their material conditions.) The 
            Hindu nationalists' attitude to the Muslims is very negative for 
            several reasons. First, they number over a hundred million and 
            constitute perhaps the single most important vote bank against Hindu 
            nationalism. Second, the presence of two Muslim majority states -- 
            Pakistan and Bangladesh -- as immediate neighbors makes the 
            relationship between the Hindu majority and the Muslim minority 
            uneasy, ambivalent, and even tricky. Third, Hindu nationalists hold 
            the Muslims responsible for the vivisection of India, the sacred and 
            ancient land of the Hindus. Fourth, Indian Muslims have not entirely 
            given up the claim to nationality even after partition, although 
            they are territorially dispersed. The effort to consolidate Muslims 
            as a nationality is pursued by projecting (although wrongly) Urdu as 
            the exclusive language of Muslims. Finally, the claim by Kashmiri 
            Muslims that Kashmir is their exclusive homeland, the secessionist 
            movement in Kashmir believed to be abetted and sustained by 
            Pakistan, the special privilege conceded to Kashmir under article 
            370 of the Indian constitution, have all soured the relationship 
            between Hindu nationalists and Muslim nationalists, eroding the 
            democratic ethos of the Indian polity. The Hindu nationalist 
            hostility to other religions is thus not simply based on their 
            "alien" origin but anchored as well to the proclivity they unfold in 
            claiming that they too are nations. Thus interreligious hostility in 
            independent India is most pronounced between Hindus, on the one 
            hand, and Sikhs and Muslims, on the other, both of whom define 
            themselves as nations or nationalities. It is important to recall 
            here that Sikhism is the youngest religion of Indian origin; 
            further, the definition of Hinduism proffered by the Indian 
            Constitution, the Hindu Code Bill, and Hindu nationalists includes 
            Sikhism along with Jainism and Buddhism. Hinduism, although not 
            proselytizing, is migratory. At least twelve million Hindus live 
            outside the Indian subcontinent (Jain 1989:299-304), the traditional 
            sacred land of Hinduism. In some of the countries (e.g., Fiji, 
            Surinam, Mauritius) they constitute majorities. Would it be correct 
            to say that those Hindus who have settled outside the Indian 
            subcontinent cease to be Hindus because they do not live in their 
            ancestral homeland? The absurdity of the question is patent, but it 
            emanates from the assumptions made by Hindu nationalists. At any 
            rate, where does one put agnostics, rationalists and secularists in 
            the scheme of Hindu Rashtra or, for that matter, in any nation 
            constructed on the basis of religion? Finally, the Hindu nationalist 
            claim implies the annexation of Nepal, the Hindu majority neighbor, 
            as a part of consolidating the Hindu nation! It is also not true 
            that only Islam and Christianity have colonized new territories and 
            in that process either annihilated or marginalized native 
            populations. The dominant religions of Sri Lanka are Buddhism and 
            Hinduism (both of Indian origin), and the original inhabitants of 
            the country, the Veddas, constitute just one percent of Sri Lankan 
            population today. In the process of Aryanizing India, the native 
            population was stigmatized. Buddhism has been vigorously 
            proselytizing, and Hinduism acutely assimilative. Therefore, 
            religion-territory conterminality is not axiomatic even in the case 
            of religions of Indian origin. The Hindus belong to a multiplicity 
            of speech communities; that is, there are several Hindu nations. To 
            grapple with this problem, Hindu nationalists project Sanskrit as 
            the common ancient language of all Hindus and Hindi written in 
            Devnagri script as the national language of India. But they 
            encounter several difficulties and severe resistance in this context 
            (Oommen 1990a:43-66). First, Sanskrit is not a living language and 
            is today spoken only by a handful of people. Second, it is not true 
            that Sanskrit is the exclusive heritage of Hindus; it is a common 
            Indian heritage cutting across religious categories. While Sanskrit 
            was an ancient and highly developed language of ancient India, so 
            were Pali and Tamil. (Of these three languages only Tamil is a 
            living vibrant language.) Given the above, Sanskrit is at best 
            identified with Aryan Hinduism, Pali with Buddhism, and Tamil with 
            Dravidian Hinduism. Consequently, Sanskrit is not even the common 
            heritage of all Hindus. Third, Hindi, even as it is expansively 
            defined to include several languages and dialects, is spoken by only 
            38 percent of the Indian population. Fourth, several of the 
            Indo-Aryan languages (e.g., Bengali, Marathi) and all the major 
            Dravidian languages are equally if not more developed as compared 
            with Hindi; and these non-Hindi speech communities do not accept 
            Hindi as the exclusive "national" language, relegating their own 
            mother tongues to the background. Finally, there are a dozen highly 
            developed languages in India with ten million or more speakers; in 
            fact, some of them have as many as fifty million speakers. There is 
            no possibility of these nations abandoning their languages in favor 
            of Hindi just to facilitate establishing a Hindu nation. The 
            fallacious claim about religion-territory conterminality is also 
            implied in the claims advanced by Muslims and Sikhs that they are 
            nations. As hinted above, the alien migrant element in the Muslim 
            population of South Asia is negligible, and the overwhelming 
            majority of Muslims are converts from local castes and tribes. 
            Therefore, the claims of Muslims that particular areas of the Indian 
            subcontinent are their homeland is legitimate and authentic because 
            they have a moral claim on these territories, although not as 
            Muslims. If the Muslims were not natives and mere migrants eager to 
            return to their homeland (as the Jews did in the wake of the Zionist 
            movement), they would not have succeeded in staking their claim. But 
            there are several difficulties in advancing the claim that Muslims 
            qua Muslims constitute a nation. First, none of the areas claimed by 
            the Muslims as their homeland (as in the case of other religious 
            groups) was populated exclusively by them even after substantial 
            transfer d Hindu and Sikh populations from these areas. Therefore, 
            the claim that these areas were or are Muslim homelands is not 
            tenable -- not because Islam is an "alien" religion, but because 
            nativity and nationhood cannot be defined in terms of religious 
            faiths and affiliations. The so-called Muslim homeland is as much 
            the homeland of non-Muslims of that region. Second, even if a 
            section of the Muslims are migrants to India, to the extent that (a) 
            the migration occurred several centuries ago and since (b) they 
            identify with the territory presently inhabited by them as their 
            homeland, the claim ought to be accepted as legitimate. Because 
            there are several alien elements among Hindus -- Kashmiri Pandits, 
            Maghi Brahmins, Rajputs to mention but a few -- whose nativity is 
            not questioned by Hindu nationalists, this is no concession to the 
            alien elements in the Muslim population. Third, Pakistan, which 
            emerged in 1947, although populated predominantly by Muslims, could 
            not be sustained as one "nation" for long because of the absence of 
            geographical contiguity and linguistic uniformity. In fact, Islam 
            became an irrelevant variable in maintaining the unity of Muslim 
            Pakistan, leading to its split mainly based on territory and 
            language. Fourth, the Hindi-speaking Muslims, popularly referred to 
            as Bihari Muslims, instantly became alien elements in Bangladesh, 
            the state of the Bengali-speaking Muslims. Even the Hindi/Urdu 
            speaking Muslims who migrated to Pakistan from India are not 
            accepted as natives and remain Mohajirins, the stigmatized 
            outsiders. Thus Muslim nationalists deny nativity even to 
            co-religionists who are migrants from outside. This clearly points 
            to the antidemocratic tenor of religious nationalism. Fifth, the 
            predominantly Muslim but multilingual Pakistan continues to have 
            serious tensions and conflicts among its different linguistic groups 
            -- Punjabis, Sindhis, Baluchis, and so on -- that is, the nations 
            that constitute the state of Pakistan. Each of these collectivities 
            defines its respective linguistic region as its homeland. Thus it is 
            clear that homeland can be anchored only to speech communities and 
            not to faith communities. Once India was partitioned, no territory 
            within India could be claimed as a Muslim homeland, save the Kashmir 
            valley. However, this claim is ambivalent for two reasons. First, 
            Kashmir itself is partitioned and apportioned between India and 
            Pakistan for geopolitical reasons. Second, there are others in 
            Kashmir (e.g., Kashmiri Pandits) who stake their claim with equal 
            intensity and authenticity that Kashmir is their homeland too. In 
            such a situation the only route available to those who falsely claim 
            that the Kashmir valley is an exclusive Muslim homeland is to 
            intimidate, terrorize, and flush out those who make counterclaims. 
            In the current exodus of Kashmiri Pandits from Kashmir what one 
            witnesses is the inevitable consequence of the perverse notion that 
            there exists conterminality between territory and religion, that is, 
            territorialization of religion. Admittedly, territorialization of 
            religion leads to ethnification of minority or weak nations. After 
            partition, the Muslims of India did not have a decisive majority in 
            any part of India except in the Kashmir valley and the Laccadives 
            and Minicoy Islands. But Muslims constituted about 12 percent of 
            India's population, amounting to around seventy million people in 
            the 1950s. That is, while their absolute number was substantial, 
            they were thinly dispersed all over the country. This situation was 
            susceptible to their getting assimilated within the linguistic 
            regions (nations) they inhabit. This necessitated the invention and 
            maintenance of new symbols to preserve their socioreligious 
            identity. Urdu, written in Persian-Arabic script, is the most 
            important symbol the Muslims invoke to highlight their cultural 
            specificity and nationality within India. But the project remains 
            ineffective in investing nationhood on Muslims on an all-India basis 
            because the principle of geographical contiguity is imperiled. The 
            language of the majority of Muslims in India is not Urdu; it is only 
            in two provinces -- Uttar Pradesh and Bihar -- that one finds 
            Muslims who are also Urdu speakers. These two states account for 
            only one-third of the Muslim population and one-half of the Urdu 
            speakers in India. In Jammu and Kashmir, though the official 
            language is Urdu, the Urdu speakers of the state count a meager 0.27 
            percent. On the other hand, the majority of the Urdu speakers are 
            from states where the proportion of Muslims is very low. This 
            disjuncture between Urdu and Islam has further muted the possibility 
            of Urdu nationalism emerging as an authentic force in independent 
            India (cf. Brass 1974). The Sikh claim to nationhood, too, assumes 
            religion-territory conterminality. But the Punjab, claimed to be the 
            Sikh homeland, was a Muslim-majority province before India's 
            partition, with 51 percent Muslims in 1921. By 1961, although the 
            Muslim population was reduced to a mere two percent in the Indian 
            Punjab (both because of the re-allocation of territory and 
            migration), the Sikhs constituted only 33 percent, and the Hindus 
            were still in majority with 64 percent. As religion was not accepted 
            as the basis of constituting politico-administrative units in 
            independent India, the only hope was to carve out a Sikh majority 
            province by invoking language as the criterion. The Sikh leadership 
            therefore staked their claim for a separate province based on 
            Punjabi language. A separate Punjabi-speaking state was formed in 
            1966 in which the Sikhs constituted only a thin majority of 53 
            percent. Thus, in spite of two successive partitions, the Punjab 
            still cannot be viewed as the exclusive homeland of Sikhs; they do 
            not constitute a decisive demographic majority, and the remaining 47 
            percent of non-Sikh population, too, considers Punjab as its 
            homeland. But, a fatal error by Punjabi Hindus in disclaiming their 
            real mothertongue -- namely, Punjabi -- and on falsely insisting 
            that Hindi is their mothertongue provided a thin veneer of 
            legitimacy to the crystallization of the idea that the Punjab is the 
            Sikh homeland (see Nayyar 1966). There is another reason why the 
            Sikh claim to the Punjab as their homeland is untenable. Although 78 
            percent of the Sikhs of India live in Punjab, the remaining 22 
            percent are dispersed all over India. This demographic dispersal of 
            Sikhs may be traced to two factors. First, in the wake of partition 
            a substantial proportion of the Sikhs who migrated to India settled 
            outside the Punjab. Second, the Sikhs are an enterprising migratory 
            community in search of economic opportunities. The logical corollary 
            of insisting that Punjab is the exclusive homeland of the Sikhs is 
            to render instantly the Sikhs outside Punjab and the non-Sikhs 
            inside Punjab aliens, outsiders, and refugees. The point I want to 
            make is this: claims to nationhood by a people are based on their 
            moral claim on a specific territory as their homeland. Such a claim 
            cannot be sustained by a religious collectivity because of the 
            disjuncture between religion and territory. Pursuantly, the claim to 
            nationhood by Hindus, Muslims and Sikhs based on the assumption and 
            argument that the whole of India or specific parts of India 
            constitute their exclusive homeland is untenable. Viewed thus, 
            religious nationalities are not simply imagined communities (cf. 
            Anderson 1983) but also authoritarian collectivities. 
            COMMUNALIZATION Once the untenable assumption that a religious 
            collectivity is a nation is accepted, an appropriate strategy, 
            namely, communalization of politics, has to be invoked. Communalism 
            has a positive as well as a negative referent. In South Asia, 
            communalism is invariably viewed as a negative force as it is 
            juxtaposed against nationalism; it may be defined as the tendency on 
            the part of a religious collectivity to claim that it is a political 
            community (Dumout 1970). It is necessary and useful to distinguish 
            between at least three different variants of communalism as a 
            political force as they fall into a hierarchy of threat to the state 
            (Oommen 1990a: 112-23). First, a religious community defines itself 
            as an autonomous political community, that is, an entity entitled to 
            have its own state. This implies secession from the state to which 
            it is currently attached and hence may be designated as secessionist 
            communalism. The Muslim demand for Pakistan and the Sikh demand for 
            Khalistan are examples of this variety of communalism. The second 
            variant of communalism is the proclivity on the part of the 
            religious collectivity to define itself as a nation, that is, as a 
            cultural entity with a territorial base. This is often articulated 
            in the argument that in order to maintain its cultural specificity 
            the nation should have a separate politico-administrative 
            arrangement, which could be a district or a province within the 
            federal polity.(8) The demand for a separate Punjabi Suba, although 
            couched in linguistic terms, was essentially a demand for a separate 
            Sikh province within India. To the extent that the demand is geared 
            to preserve the cultural specificity of a religious collectivity and 
            a separate province is viewed as a tool to achieve that end, this 
            type of communalism may be designated as separatist communalism. The 
            third variant is the demand by a religious collectivity to be 
            recognized as a specific entity suffering from material 
            deprivations, the eradication of which could be met through measures 
            such as political representation, employment quotas, distribution of 
            land, industrial licenses, and so on. In this context, mobilization 
            of the religious collectivity is attempted as an interest group 
            geared to the welfare of its members. Therefore, this variety of 
            communalism may be labeled welfarist communalism. I am persuaded to 
            distinguish between these three types of communalisms because their 
            implications vary vastly for the state, the nation, and the 
            religious community. The three types of communalism can be organized 
            on a continuum of hierarchy of threat to the state, and consequently 
            state responses differ radically in each case (Oommen 
            1990b:183-209). Generally speaking, the state would oppose tooth and 
            nail secessionist communalism and would spare no effort to liquidate 
            the movement. This can be easily discerned in the response of the 
            Indian state and Hindu nationalists to secessionist movements in the 
            Punjab and in Kashmir. The opposition to separatist communalism is 
            less virulent. If the mobilization by the concerned religious 
            community is massive and visible and if the countermobilization by 
            the opposing community is weak, the state in all probability would 
            concede the demand. The formation of the Punjabi Suba exemplifies 
            this pattern of response. Finally, governments of multireligious 
            democratic societies are compelled to allow religious collectivities 
            to function as interest groups and to concede the demands they make. 
            This response pattern is called for either because the demands made 
            are perceived as legitimate or because the political clout of the 
            community as a vote bank is substantial. The state response to the 
            demands made by religious minorities in the context of the policy of 
            protective discrimination (e.g., bringing the neo-Buddhists under 
            the purview of the reservation policy), providing the requisite 
            recognition to languages claimed by religious minorities as a part 
            of their cultural heritage (e.g., the recognition given to Urdu), or 
            "protecting" the minorities from "intimidations" of the state legal 
            system (nonimplementation of a uniform civil code) are examples of 
            the Indian state recognizing religious collectivities as 
            "legitimate" interest groups. Of the three communalisms listed above 
            two imply religion-territory association. Thus, secessionist 
            communalism is geared to the establishment of an exclusive state for 
            the religious collectivity, which implies its legal claim over its 
            presumed homeland. In the case of separatist communalism, the claim 
            over the homeland by the religious collectivity is essentially moral 
            in that the "nation" is to function within the territorial 
            boundaries of the multinational state of which it is a part. 
            However, a religious community operates merely as an interest group 
            when it recognizes the impossibility of carving out a separate state 
            or nation for itself because it cannot stake and sustain any legal 
            or moral claim on a contiguous territory. Generally speaking the 
            interest group orientation and demographic dispersal of a religious 
            group within the territory controlled by the state coincide. The 
            point to be noted is that the nature and content of communalism is 
            inextricably bound up with the religious collectivity's territorial 
            base and spread, which in turn has profound implications for the 
            polity. If secessionist communalism invariably invites state 
            repression, welfarist communalism usually augments democratic 
            culture. Separatist communalism may graduate into secessionist or 
            may be scaled down into welfarist depending upon the manner in which 
            the demands are framed and articulated, and on the state response to 
            them. That is, the nature of the state -- democratic or 
            authoritarian -- and the style of framing and pursuing the demands 
            by the mobilized collectivities will critically mold the process. 
            HOMOGENIZATION The claim to nationhood or nationality by a religious 
            collectivity willy nilly implies the process of cultural 
            homogenization, that is, evolving and imposing a common life-style. 
            In independent India this has been articulated in different contexts 
            and forms. I shall pursue the present discussion with special 
            reference to Hindus and Sikhs, and this for two reasons. First, the 
            claim to nationhood by these religious collectivities has not yet 
            been realized, unlike the case of the Muslims in the Indian 
            subcontinent. Second, the Hindus and Sikhs were, and to a certain 
            extent even today are, sharing a common life-style; yet every effort 
            is made to overemphasize their specificities, while ignoring the 
            commonalities. The Hindu advocacy of homogenization has been 
            articulated in different ways. If in the 1960s and the 1970s the 
            preferred phrase was "Indianization," now it is "Hindutva." Hindu 
            nationalists insist that the advocacy is disassociated from and 
            devoid of any narrow religious context and content but refers to a 
            lifestyle common to the people of India as a whole; hence, a Hindu 
            is one who follows this life-style. If life-style includes matters 
            of dress, food, worship styles, art forms, marriage and family 
            patterns, there is very little common even to the Hindus of 
            different regional-linguistic areas, not to speak of the different 
            religious communities of India. This, however, is not to deny that 
            there exists a civilizational unity encompassing the multiplicity of 
            the collectivities inhabiting India, but this envelops the people of 
            South Asia as a whole and is not confined to the Indian 
            state-society. Perhaps an example will lend clarity to the point I 
            am making. Brahmins constitute the only pan-Indian Varna (Caste), 
            and even they differ vastly in, say, food habits. Thus if the 
            majority of Brahmins traditionally were vegetarians, the Bengali 
            Brahmin was a fish-eater and the Kashmiri Pandit a meat-eater. That 
            is, vegetarianism is not common to all Hindus, not even to Brahmins. 
            But beef is a taboo for believing Hindus, and they do not consume 
            it. (The fact that beef was not a taboo in ancient India and it 
            constituted a part of the regular diet is not relevant here.) 
            Against this background it is important to recall that there have 
            been several mobilizations against cow slaughter in "secular" 
            independent India, emphasizing the fact that the cow is a sacred 
            animal for Hindus. But beef is not taboo for Muslims and Christians 
            who together constitute a staggering one hundred and twenty million 
            people in India. Thus, it is not only the case that a common 
            life-style for the entire population of India is advocated, but 
            through that advocacy only Hindu beliefs and sentiments are sought 
            to be preserved and imposed on others, which undermines India's 
            cultural diversity and democratic possibilities. There is another 
            context in which the advocacy of homogenization surfaces in India, 
            namely, that of a common civil code. It should be noted here that a 
            common civil code for Indian citizens is a constitutional promise, 
            and liberals, secularists, rationalists, atheists, and so on, also 
            support its implementation. But when a uniform civil code is 
            advocated by Hindu nationalists the conservative elements among the 
            religious minorities perceive in that a threat to preserving their 
            cultural identity. It is useful to remind ourselves that the Hindu 
            conservatives resisted tooth and nail the introduction and 
            implementation of the Hindu Code Bill because they feared that the 
            Bill would erode the specific cultural identity of the Hindu 
            community (Smith 1963). On the other hand, the fact that a commonly 
            applicable Hindu Code Bill was required to be formulated points to 
            the very diversity of Hinduism as it existed in different regions 
            and among various communities of India. Religious diversity begets 
            legal pluralism. In those state-societies which are unireligious and 
            unidenominational, it is relatively easier to implement a uniform 
            civil code. The resistance to religious reforms in such societies 
            comes from the conservatives of the same religious collectivity. 
            Furthermore, there is a qualitative difference in the conflicts 
            between "conservatives" and "reformers" drawn from the same 
            religious community and the confrontations between people of two 
            different religious collectivities, whatever may be the content of 
            the contentious issue. Herein lies the problematic of cultural 
            homogenization being advocated by the Hindu nationalists through the 
            implementation of a uniform civil code in a multireligious society 
            like India. There is another aspect to the implementation of a 
            uniform civil code by the state in a multireligious society, which 
            is that it endorses, perhaps unwittingly, the definition of the 
            state as an entity commanding terminal loyalty from its citizens, a 
            definition in tune with the reality of unireligious states. Insofar 
            as all citizens of a state belonged to the same religious 
            collectivity such a formulation did not pose much of a problem. In 
            western nation-states, to the extent that there is an agreed 
            division of labor between the state and the church, the notion of 
            terminal loyalty is understood as political loyalty. For example, in 
            matters religious, Catholics who are distributed into numerous 
            state-societies may have their terminal loyalty to the Roman 
            Catholic church and its ecclesiastical order headed by the Pope and 
            not to the secular authority of the state of which they are 
            citizens. To those religious communities whose co-religionists are 
            distributed across different state-societies and who have a common 
            religious authority, the idea of terminal loyalty to the state, 
            particularly when the state is not governed by their co-religionists 
            according to the injunctions of the religious texts, would be 
            anathema. Herein lies the source of rupture in the Hindu 
            nationalist's advocacy of a uniform civil code and its resistance by 
            conservative elements, particularly among Muslims and Christians. 
            The state in independent India has not yet mustered sufficient 
            courage to introduce the constitutionally promised Uniform Civil 
            Code, but it did implement the Hindu Code Bill in spite of 
            resistance from conservative Hindu elements. This reinforces the 
            point I made above, namely, that there is a qualitative difference 
            between the resistance encountered from conservative co-religionists 
            and that emanating from those of other religious faiths. It is 
            important to note here that this differential orientation of the 
            state to the religious collectivities does adversely affect the 
            democratic milieu. The Hindu nationalist project of homogenization 
            is caught in a trap of Hinduism's internal contradiction because 
            homogenization implies not only uniformity but also equality. The 
            Hindutva version of homogeneity, however, while appealing to the 
            non-Hindu minorities to shed their cultural identity, assimilate 
            with the mainstream and become full-fledged Indians, is either 
            reluctant or else ambivalent, to grapple with the institutionalized 
            inequality within the Hindu social system as embodied in the 
            institution of caste. Indeed, several strategies are invoked to 
            manage this tension and camouflage this contradiction: first, 
            denying that caste system and particularly untouchability are parts 
            of traditional Hinduism and insisting that these are latterday 
            accretions resulting from praxiological aberrations rather than 
            imperfect doctrines; second, conceding the need to scissor away 
            these negative accretions through gradual piecemeal reformism; 
            third, organizing reformist collective actions and mobilizations 
            (e.g., intercaste dining, collective worship) to fraternalize the 
            deprived and sap them of their protest orientation. However, given 
            the fact that the constituency of the Hindutva ideology is largely 
            confined to the twice-born Hindus of the Hindi belt, it has failed 
            to gain the confidence of the Dravidian Hindus, the Other Backward 
            Classes, the Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes, together 
            constituting the majority of the Indian population. Thus the Hindu 
            project of homogenization is bound to remain limited in its scope 
            unless it frontally grapples with the issue of institutionalized 
            inequality within Hinduism. The Sikh project of cultural 
            homogenization is more successful because, (a) the Sikhs are a 
            minority, (b) they are unilingual, and (c) Sikhism is more 
            egalitarian in its value orientation. Yet, the attempt at 
            homogenization faces, and is likely to face, several obstacles. 
            First, the dominant agent of Sikh nationalism is the Jat peasantry 
            anchored in rural areas. In the event of Sikh religious nationalism 
            succeeding in wresting a state for itself, the "protection" now 
            available particularly to the Mazbhi (Scheduled Caste) and the 
            Nirankari (a sect not recognized by the Sikh ecclesiastical 
            authority) Sikhs, from the Indian state as well as from the 
            all-India political parties will disappear. Understandably, the Sikh 
            segments that are likely to perceive the emergence of a Sikh state 
            as a sure invitation to Jat domination are likely to put obstacles 
            in the process of homogenization. Second, the Sikh project of 
            homogenization would inevitably mean the current freedom available 
            to Sahajdharis (shaven ones) will diminish. Not only will the 
            insistence on being Keshdharis (unshorn ones) intensify, but in all 
            probability brute force would be pressed into service to transform 
            the "deviants" into conformists. In fact, available evidence 
            suggests that even Keshdharis will be forced to follow a more 
            rigorous and puritan life-style (e.g., abjuring smoking). 
            Inevitably, organized resistance to such codes of conduct would 
            eventually crystallize when the insistence on homogenization becomes 
            more intense and authoritarian. Third, the urban, secular, 
            middle-class professionals, bureaucrats, and intellectuals (both 
            Keshdharis and Sahajdharis) are likely to be indifferent, if not 
            hostile, to the efforts to introduce a more uniform life-style. 
            Pushed to the wall they may even articulate their opposition. These 
            spokes in the wheel of homogenization may abort the fruition of Sikh 
            religious nationalism. Apart from the specific factors listed above 
            to demonstrate the untenability of homogenization pursued by the 
            Hindu and Sikh nationalists, there are several general reasons why 
            homogenization cannot be pursued particularly in a democratic and 
            culturally plural society. I shall list only three of them (Oommen 
            1992:154). First, to homogenize invariably means to establish the 
            hegemony of the dominant collectivity, with the attendant 
            annihilation of the weak and minority collectivities or at best 
            their assimilation into an artificially contrived cultural 
            mainstream, leading to the eclipse of their identity. Second, most 
            state-societies, as they are constituted, draw their population from 
            diverse sources. Therefore, assimilation and annihilation endanger 
            the principle of diversity and block the task of developing 
            pluralism and democracy. Third, contemporary societies are 
            constantly exposed to alien influences and hence characterized by 
            frayed edges and loose textures. The ongoing process of 
            globalization is bound to intensify this trend. In such a situation 
            the only viable option is to celebrate diversity, foster pluralism, 
            nurture intergroup equality, and reinforce democratic trends. 
            RELATIVIZATION It is fairly clear by now that cultural relativism is 
            a necessary corollary of homogenization. Relativization is the 
            tendency to rehabilitate tradition in its totality in terms of 
            original vision and purity. It often provides justification to all 
            kinds of inhuman and disparaging practices (see Redfield 1957), be 
            it sati (the practice of the Hindu wife committing suicide by 
            jumping into the funeral pyre of her husband), untouchability, 
            maintenance of perticular diets, dress patterns, and so on, all of 
            which are justified in the name of religion. Thus, cultural 
            relativism in the context of religion has two dimensions. First, it 
            advocates values and practices that are patently inhuman and 
            irrational in the contemporary context. Second, it insists on 
            practices that are incongruous and anomalous in modern society, 
            which practices are justified by invoking religious texts formulated 
            and injunctions adumbrated in an entirely different context. This is 
            often referred to as religious "fundamentalism," which may be 
            defined as the tendency to adhere to the text ignoring the context. 
            The Hindu conservative elements often justify and legitimize 
            practices such as sati and untouchability in the name of tradition 
            and values of pristine Hinduism. The Sikh adherence to the keeping 
            of the five Ks -- Kesh (unshorn hair and beard), Kanga (comb), Kachh 
            (knee-length pair of breeches), Karah (steel bracelet), and Kirpan 
            (sword) -- also smacks of religious relativism. Admittedly, 
            religious relativism fosters inequality and advocates anachronistic 
            life-styles. The ideology of homogenization, then, is not only 
            geared to the standardization of values, norms and practices, but it 
            also implies (a) the revival of obsolescent traditional values, 
            norms and practices that are not relevant to the present, and (b) 
            the imposition of those values on others, both "deviant" 
            co-religionists and religious minorities. This is so because the 
            reference point of homogenization advocated by religious 
            nationalists invariably relates to the original vision and practices 
            of their rounding fathers, ignoring the context of the latter's 
            advocacy. That is, religious nationalisms carry with them the 
            inevitable tendency of revivalism. Further, religious nationalists 
            endeavor to create a societal ethos buttressed by the values of the 
            dominant religion within the state-society. Neither Hindu nor Sikh 
            nationalism is an exception to this inherent tendency; therefore 
            neither is likely to survive in a modernizing world, nor are other 
            religious nationalisms. CONCLUSION The gist of my argument is that 
            religious nationalism as a project is bound to fail because its 
            domain assumptions -- namely, that there is conterminality between 
            religion and territory and that a religious collectivity is a 
            political community -- are wrong and empirically unsustainable. The 
            process of cultural homogenization is a prerequisite to encapsulate 
            and contain all the religious groups within the ken of religious 
            nationalism. This in practice means imposing the life-style of the 
            majority over the minority religious groups. Further, given the fact 
            that the frame of reference of religious nationalisms is invariably 
            anchored to what is believed to be the original vision of the 
            founding fathers, it necessarily prompts relativism, that is, 
            reviving and preserving the traditional beliefs and rituals even as 
            they are embedded in unjust and inhuman values. Admittedly, 
            religious nationalism carries with it the seeds of religious 
            fundamentalism. For these reasons religious nationalism is not 
            sustainable in a fast globalizing world in which democracy has 
            emerged as a universally accepted and acclaimed value. 1 About 27 
            percent of the member-states of the United Nations have a population 
            of one million or less, and 54 percent have five million or less. 
            Many of these entities are not economically viable and can sustain 
            themselves only as client-states. The way out seems to be to form 
            multinational states. 2 Notwithstanding the well-known fact that the 
            terms Hindus and Hinduism are appellations invented by conquering or 
            colonizing outsiders to refer to the inhabitants of the then India, 
            today these are terms that connote a particular religious 
            collectivity and a corpus of belief system and ritual practices 
            specific to them. It could be argued, with some justification, that 
            notions such as religious collectivity, belief system, and so on, 
            are scarcely applicable to Hindus and Hinduism. Extrapolating the 
            Thomas theorem, I suggest that if the people who define themselves 
            as Hindus assert that Hinduism is their religion their perception 
            should be endorsed as authentic. At any rate, it is those who assert 
            that Hinduism is a religion who have emerged as its accredited 
            spokespersons. 3 According to the Hindu doctrine of creation, 
            Brahmins emerged from the mouth of the creator, Kshatriyas from the 
            hands, Vaishyas from the thighs, and Shudras from the feet. This 
            chaturvarna (four color) scheme does not even account for the 
            untouchables, belonging to the fifth varna. 4 The four-hundred or so 
            tribal communities of India claim that they are the original 
            inhabitants (Adivasis) of the land. This claim is not accepted by 
            Hindu nationalists, who insist that Aryan Hindus were the original 
            settlers and consequently label the tribal communities as 
            forest-dwellers (Vanvasis). 5 The population of India speaks 
            languages belonging to four families: Indo-Aryan (73%), Dravidian 
            (25%), Austro-Asiatic (1.5%), and Tibeto-Chinese (0.5%). Dravidian 
            languages are spoken mainly in the four South Indian states: Kerala 
            (Malayalam), Karnataka (Kannada), Tamil Nadu (Tamil), and Andhra 
            Pradesh (Telugu). The Dravidian movement, which opposed Aryan 
            domination, considers Dravidian Hinduism distinct from Aryan 
            Hinduism. 6 This figure is problematic because the Indian census 
            automatically counts all those who do not belong to one of the world 
            religions as Hindu. In the British Indian census there was a 
            religious category variously designated as "animist," "tribal" 
            "primitive," etc., which counted two to three percent of the 
            population, which was about twenty-five million people in those 
            days. This category is absorbed under the rubric of Hinduism from 
            the 1951 census onward. 7 It may, however, be noted that the Baha'is 
            did pursue the project of proselytization in the 1960s in the region 
            of Malwa in central India. Consequently, their number increased from 
            a small figure in the 1950s to 400,000 (see Garlington 1977). 8 Thus 
            Kushwant Singh writes: "The only chance of survival of the Sikhs as 
            a separate community is to create a state in which they form a 
            compact group, where the teaching of gurumukhi and the Sikh religion 
            is compulsory where there is an atmosphere of respect for the 
            traditions of their Khalsa forefathers" (1966:305). REFERENCES 
            Anderson, B. 1983. Imagined Communities. Bombay: New Left. Brass, P. 
            1974. Religion, Language and Politics in North India. Delhi: Vikas 
            Publishing House. Dumont, L. 1970. Religion, Politics and History in 
            India. The Hague: Mouton. Garlington, W. 1977. "The Baha'i faith in 
            Malwa," pp. 101-18 in G. A. Oddie (ed.), Religion in South Asia, 
            Delhi: Manohar. Gellner, E. 1983. Nations and Nationalism. Ithaca, 
            NY: Cornell University Press. Golwalkar, M. S. 1939. We or Our 
            Nationhood Defined. Nagpur: Bharat Prakashan. Goyal, D. R. 1979. 
            Rashtriya Swayam Sewak Sangh. Delhi: Radhakrishna. Hertz, F. 1944. 
            Nationality in History and Politics. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, 
            Trubner. Jain, P. C. 1989. "Indians abroad." Economic and Political 
            Weekly 17:229-304. Miller, D. 1991. The Reason of Metaphor. New 
            Delhi: Sage. Nayyar, B. R. 1966. Minority Politics in the Punjab. 
            Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Oommen, T. K. 1990a. 
            State and Society in India. New Delhi: Sage. -----. 1990b. Protest 
            and Change. New Delhi: Sage. -----. 1992. "Reconciling pluralism and 
            equality." International Review of Sociology 1 (New Series): 141-72. 
            -----. 1994. "State, nation and ethnie," forthcoming in P. Ratcliffe 
            (ed.), Race, Ethnicity and Nation. London: University College London 
            Press. Pandey, G. 1990. The Colonial Construction of Communalism in 
            North India. Delhi: Oxford University Press. Redfield, R. 1957. The 
            Primitive World and its Transformation. Ithaca, NY: Cornell 
            University Press. Savarkar, V. D. 1949. Hindutva. Pune: S. R. Poona. 
            Singh, K. 1966. History of the Sikhs. Princeton, NJ: Princeton 
            University Press. Smith, D. E. 1963. India as a Secular State. 
            Bombay: Oxford University Press. Weber, M. 1948. From Max Weber. 
            London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.