ON THE POSSIBILITY OF SELF-TRANSCENDENCE:

PHILOSOPHICAL COUNSELING, ZEN, AND THE PSYCHOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVE
Rachel B. Blass
Journal of Chinese Philosophy Vol.23 1996
PP.277-297
Copyright @1996 by Dialogue Publishing Company, Honolulu,
Hawaii, U.S.A.


. P.277 Abstract: This paper distinguishes between two conceptions of philosophical counseling. The one focuses on the clarification of the individual's psychological and philosophical self and the other on the transcendence of that self. A comparison of the latter conception with the self-transcendence that takes place through Zen Buddhism contributes to the examination of the question of whether philosophical counseling can indeed overcome potential psychological obstacles to attaining a transcendent aim. Possible influences of the integration of psychological intervention into the philosophical search for transcendence are also discussed. Since the first emergence of philosophical counseling as a form of professional practice in Germany in the early nineteen eighties, there have been a number of attempts to define its domain. So far no conclusive consensual definition has been formulated, nor does there appear to be agreement even on the essential ingredients that must be present in order for an encounter between two people to be considered philosophical counseling. In the course of this paper I will focus on one central line of thought within philosophical counseling. This line considers the philo- P.278 sophical counseling encounter to be characterized by a quest for transcending one's self. The counselor is viewed in this context as a guide who, through philosophical means, facilitates a process within the counselee in which the counselee steps beyond the course set out for him by his psychological makeup. In this respect there is similarity between philosophical counseling and Zen, which too seeks to go beyond the psychological self to attain a true state of being. An understanding of the relationship between philosophical counseling and Zen will help explore the question of whether in philosophical counseling transcendence is indeed possible, as well as the nature of the difficulties that may stand in its way. TWO BASIC CONCEPTIONS OF PHILOSOPHICAL COUNSELING: CLARIFICATION VS. TRANSCENDENCE Many present day philosophical counselors consider Socrates to be the spiritual father of their profession. They view philosophical counseling as a renewal of his early attempts to help others examine their lives in a philosophical way. But now, fifteen years since this renewal began, it has become apparent that there is little agreement as to what is to be meant by ''helping others examine their lives philosophically". There is a great diversity among the different practitioners, in their attempts to characterize philosophical counseling. Many of these attempts take place by comparing philosophical counseling with other helping professions, most notably psychotherapy. Achenbach, the founder of philosophical counseling, and his followers have characterized philosophical counseling as an approach which does not use methods, techniques, and assumptions-as presumably psychotherapy does-but rather examines these critically (Achenbach, 1984, 1995) . In contrast, some philosophical counselors have stressed that what is unique to their form of help is the application of specifically philosophical skills, tools, knowledge, and methods, to the alleviation of the individual's distress or P. 279 to the resolution of the problem he is facing (e.g., Cohen, 1995). Another view is that what characterizes the help that philosophical counseling has to offer is precisely the fact that it is not directed toward the amelioration of distress or resolution of problems but rather toward the philosophical understanding of these (e.g., Veening, 1994) . Others have considered philosophical counseling to be defined by its subject matter (e.g., Lahav, 1994; Schefczyk, 1994;). Here the claim is that in contrast to psychotherapy which is concerned with psychological processes and mechanisms which exist within the individual's mind, philosophical counseling is concerned with conceptual issues that arise from the individual's life, but do not exist within his mind. And still other philosophical counselors have stressed that what characterizes the philosophical encounter is the kind of symmetric nonauthoritarian relationship that the counselor offers the counselee (e.g., Tillmans, 1994; Lindseth, 1990), and so on and so forth. My examination of the numerous sub-approaches that have evolved, only a few of which I have mentioned here, has led me to realize that they can generally be divided into two broad conceptions of philosophical counseling that pervade the field. According to one conception philosophical counseling is a process of clarification, while according to the other it is a process of transcendence. In a word, according to the former, philosophical counseling aims at clarifying the counselee's present way of being. In contrast, the latter approach attempts to aid the counselee in going beyond his present way of being into a new one. Thus, the former may seek to clarify the person's way of being by uncovering, examining and possibly modifying presuppositions hidden in the person's attitude, various potentialities and implications of his situation, concepts that are interwoven in his life, ideas which he follows, ethical implications of his actions, alternative courses of action, and so on. The latter, on the other hand, would focus on the alternative way of being into which the person can evolve; on creating new ways of seeing, experiencing, relating, thinking. In other words, whereas the former deals with the person's present conceptual coordinates-with their understanding, sharpening, P.280 improvement, and even modification-the latter aims at transcending these and creating new such coordinates. PHILOSOPHICAL COUNSELING AS A PROCESS OF CLARIFICATION The conception of philosophical counseling as a process of clarification considers the philosophical examination of the individual's life to be one in which the counselor helps fhe counselee understand the conceptual and logical network that touches upon his life, and more specifically touches upon the issues with which he is currenty struggling. For example, the counselor may wish to help the counselee clarify the conception of authority which somehow touches upon his life. What exactly counts as "touches upon", may vary across different approaches. Depending on the counselor's specific approach, this clarification may be directed toward understanding the counselee's actual state of mind, e.g., actual thoughts and experiences-conscious or unconscious-about authority. The counselor may point to inconsistencies that exist within the counselee's concept of authority, or he may help to explore the consequences of having such a concept which the counselee had not envisioned. Perhaps holding on to a view of authorily as a rigid, unyielding and threatening force, is not beneficial to certain aims (e.g., succeeding in work), something which may be important to the counselee. Alternatively, the philosophical clarification may be directed toward a conception of authority which the counselee lives without being conscious of it, or even without having it in his mind at all. In such cases, the philosophical concept of authority is not something that exists in the counselee's mind, but may find expression, or may be embodied, in his way of life. An analogy would be a painting which may embody the concept of harmony, without that concept existing in the painter's mind. Just as the painter may create such a painting without ever thinking about the concept of harmony, a counselee may live a life that embodies a certain conception of authority without ever thinking or experiencing P.281 this coneption, either consciously or unconsciously. One way in which the counselee may recognize and understand his conception of authority is by seeing it in relationship to other available conceptions which the counselor may discuss with him. Whether the philosophical examination is applied to facts in the person's mind or to conceptual dimensions that only indirectly relate to the person's life, the counselor applies philosophical tools, methods and knowledge with the aim of clarifying the person's actual way of being. The counselor hopes to further the counselee's self-understanding and, once again depending on the counselor's personal approach, he will also, to a greater or lesser degree, hope that this understanding will assist the counselee with his predicament. Hopefully, the latter will now find new ways to deal with what is distressing him, will no longer conceive of his situation as a distressing one, will resolve his dilemma, will function rationally, etc. I am aware that within this category of philosophical counseling as a process of clairification I am bringing together a wide range of approaches, some of which are strongly opposed to others. For example, a concern with the conceptual dimension of life is markedly different from a concern with the facts that exist within the individual's mind. Indeed, in the latter case I fail to see in what ways it differs from the concern of many psychological approaches. To give another example, counseling which sees clarification or self-understanding as a goal in itself is fundamentally different from one which uses clarification as a means for making the counselee feel better. These varying approaches, nevertheless, bear a great deal of similarity when compared with the other conception of philosophical counseling which I will now outline: philosophical counseling as a process of transcendence. P.282 PHILOSOPHICAL COUNSELING AS A PROCESS OF TRANSCENDENCE According to the conception of philosophical counseling as a process of transcendence, the philosophical examination of the individual's life does not focus on the counselee's actual way of being. Rather,it is a process in which the counselor serves as a guide in the counselee's quest to go beyond his life as determined by psychological dimensions and philosophical conceptions, and to recognize in a live way a new conceptual space that opens up through a philosophical encounter. The aim here is to go beyond not only the factual psychological level of existence, but also beyond the network of concepts which the counselee is currently living. To return to our earlier example, the goal would not be merely to explore the philosophical concept of authority that is embodied in the individual's life, but to open up a new conceptual space of living and participating, in which the issue of authority in its previous form no longer exists. Through in-depth philosophical exploration, an entire reordering on the conceptual level may take place in which the concept of authority would assume a different role, would become part of one's life in a new and more meaningful way. For example, in the context of a broad shift from an individualistic conception of the self to a Buberian I-Thou conception, the counselee's view of authority may undergo a shift from authority as constituting the independent existence of the person, to authority as a dimension of inauthenticity, a breach of the participating stance in the world. In terms of the painting analogy described above, (i.e., the person's life as analogous to a painter's painting) philosophical counseling is not concerned here with the actual painting. It is concerned neither with the meanings embodied in the counselee's "painting'(i.e., his actual way of being) nor with what goes on in his mind while painting it, but rather with a novel potential painting that is not yet in existence. It sees its role as that of taking a whole new look at the painting, exploring new coordinates with which to examine and experience it, with the aim of developing a P.283 more meaningful picture. Not only will new dimensions of the picture be appreciated, but through this appreciation a whole new picture is created. One may say, a new canvas is opened up to the counselee. Admittedly, such in-depth philosophic exploration may involve a process of clarification, as in the other conception of philosophical coun- seling. Clarification of psychological dimensions, ideas, wishes, etc., would not be important in themselves here, but the clarification of the conceptual domain may. However, in contrast to the previous conception of philosophical counseling, the focus of the clarification here would not be limited to a certain issue within the already given conceptual framework of the counselee's present life. To stay with the specific issue with which the counselee comes for counseling (e.g., authority) would be to limit any possibility for rebuilding the basic conceptual coordinates which he lives. It would be like taking a new look at the painting but focusing only on the issue of harmony. Without taking into account issues of color, of form, of balance, of thematic content,of symbolism, etc., the only change that could occur would be limited to a local modification within the already existing picture. The issue with which the individual comes to philosophical counseling must thus serve as an opening to a broader philosophical exploration. All this suggests that in contrast to the clarification approach to philosophical counseling, within the transcendence approach clarification is only a possible means toward the more ambitious aim of transcendence. The focus would not be on conceptual clarification per se, nor even on clarification in the hope that it would lead to the resolution of the counselee's problems. Rather, the conceptual exploration would be one means toward going beyond oneself, both psychologically and philosophically. It should be stressed here that such clarification would be but one means towards this end. Other means may be encountering and participating in new ideas through reading, or through trying to live new conceptions. The process here is far from an abstract exploration, but rather is a live opening up to new conceptual horizons. A question that naturally arises at this point is: In what sense is P.284 this process truly transcendence? In what way is the new philosophical self(1) that is formed through this process a transcendent one? Transcendence denotes a rise above what previously existed, thus not just any change in the nature of the philosophy one lives could be considered to be so. In this context too we may see differences among philosophical counselors. The most explicit reference to the transcendent aim of philosophical counseling is to be found in the recent work of the Israeli philosophical counselor Ran Lahav. In an interview in the German journal for philosophical counseling Zeitschrift fur Philosophische Praxis (Lahav, 1995b, p. 4) he says: "Philosophical Counseling uses philosophy not just to solve specific personal problems or to make people feel better... The goal is not to repair or improve what already exists in the person, but to overcome, go beyond, uplift oneself to new dimensions of depth and wisdom". Lahav, in his extensive work in the field, has gradually shifted from an emphasis on clarificafion to an approach which aims at enabling the counselee to go beyond his personal perspective and to come to live and embody a richer, supra-personal network of meaning, which is what he regards as wisdom. According to his approach, a person's way of being, including behaviors, attitudes, emotions, desires, etc., embody a specific interpretation of his life and world, or what he calls the person's "lived understanding", "worldview", or "network of meanings". The role of the philosophical counselor is to aid the counselee in exposing the worldview which he lives, in critically examining its basis, and in putting it in the context of the horizon of other possible worldviews (Lahav, 1993, 1994, 1995a, in press). In this way the person overcomes his particular limited horizon of attitudes and opens up to the endless network of meanings, which are not tied to any specific egocentric perspective, and which underlies our actual and potential worlds. Thus, the process of transcendence aimed at here takes the person from a specific egocentric, sell-centered horizon of living to a supra-personal embodiment of wisdom. In the work of Steven Segal, a South African philosophical counselor the idea of transcendence as aim of philosophical counseling is apparent P. 285 in his use of a Heideggerian framework (Segal, 1995). According to him, the role of philosophical counseling is to uncover the person's fundamental presuppositions, question them, and transcend them toward a more authentic way of being. These social, historical, cultural and other presuppositions shape our everyday life, but they are usually hidden from view and taken for granted in our inauthentic, everyday moments. The transition to authenticity-as Segal interprets Heidegger-is achieved when one turns one's world from a taken for granted given into an issue, i.e. from involvement in it to anxious self-reflection on it, and finds one's roots in it. As an example of this process, Segal chooses the case of Tolstoy's meaning crisis and conversion to Christianity, which involved a kind of self-philosophical counseling. Segal interprets this meaning crisis as a Heideggerian anxiety, in which Tolstoy was no longer involved in his life and hence could no longer make sense of it. He started reflecting on everything he had previously taken for granted, and discovered its meaninglessness to him. His previous fundamental values-fame, money, family life, etc.-no longer meant anything to him. For our purpose it is important that Tolstoy managed to overcome his crisis and find a new meaning (through Christianity) not by using thoughts and other materials from his previous life, but by going beyond them through philosophical reflection. It was by going beyond reason and science, in which he had previously believed, that he found his new way of being. As Segal says: "In perplexity he overcame or transcended reason" (Segal 1995, p. 116) Barbara Norman, another South African philosophical counselor, is like Segal concerned with the presuppositions that underlie and shape our lives, particularly those originating from our culture (Norman, 1995). The role of the philosophical counselor is to aid counselees in "redescribing" or "re-interpreting"-in other words, creating a new understanding of-the situation in which their lives are embedded. This is done by becoming aware of the underlying conceptual framework (or "pattern of intelligibility") , largely culturally-based, and going beyond it. It is not always clear whether Norman's process of re-description is sufficiently radical to make it count as a process of transcendence. But assuming it is, P.286 what is interesting here is that it is a transcendence to a particular perspective, albeit a rather broad one which leaves much room for personal variation. The process of transcendence is directed toward what Norman refers to as "ecological" relationships. By this she means a stance of care and involvement towards one's environment, especially human environment, accompanied by awareness of one's interdependence with the rest of the world. Here Norman associates herself with Buber and with feminist writers, who portray authentic individuals in terms of their relationship to the world outside them. While here the process of transcendence is aimed toward a specifically relational way of being it would be different for different people depending on their individual circumstances and life-history. What is common to these counselors, and those who maintain a similar approach, is the notion that the authentic person does not exist within himself. Here we see the vision of some of the existentialists, most notably Heidegger and the religious existentialists, especially Jaspers and Marcel, coming alive and finding expression within the transcendent conception of philosophical counseling. Man is not man, Jaspers explains. To be a person one must go beyond oneself and the way to this transcendence is through a philosophical encounter. Jaspers writes: There is a soaring energy in the individual responsibility of listening to the whole of reality. A man's humanity depends on how deeply he gains guidance through this listening. To be a man is to become a man. (Jaspers, 1954, p. 73)(2) In comparing the two conceptions of philosophical counseling-that of clarification, and that of transcendence-it is clear that the latter conception sets itself a much more far-reaching goal. The nature of the "help" that it offers the individual is guidance to listening to what is beyond, with the aim of realizing oneself as a man not realizing what is P.287 already in one, but realizing what is beyond one through philosophical participation in what lies beyond one. As such it is unlikely that this conception of philosophical counseling will ever assume a central position among the helping professions. Its appeal will never be as popular as short-term forms of help for overcoming problems, or even as popular as long-term forms of help which delve deeply into the self. It will probably speak only to those who seek this kind of edification. One may wonder, however, whether, even for those few who yearn for it, this type of philosophical counseling can indeed realize the role to which it aspires and indeed serve as a context for guidance towards transcendence. One possible danger is that the psychological self will resist such transformation and impede the philosophical process. As we inquire into this practical question it is useful to look at, and try to learn from, another domain which has sought self-transcendence -Zen Buddhism. ZEN AND SELF-TRANSCENDENCE The writings of the great masters of Zen Buddhism teach of the distinction between what appears to be the essence of the self and what is the true essential nature of the self. The former comes close to the modern western conception of the self as the complex network of psychological forces, desires, ideas, etc. The latter, the true essential nature of the self is recognized and can be "lived" only when the former self is shed. This point is exemplified in the writings of Dogen. According to Dogen it is only by overcoming what appears to be the essence of our selfhood (in its egotistic and superficial sense), that the authentic person comes to the fore: To study the Buddha way is to study the self To study the self is to forget the self; To forget the self is to be authenticated by the myriad things, (Shobogenzo Genjo-koan, trans. Cook, 1985,p. 133) P.288 Being a self(in the authentic sense of the term) involves an experienced unity of subject and object, of "I" and other, one that transcends not only the egocentric self but transcends the species as well. That is, this selfhood is non-anthropocentric, expressing a kind of continuity between things and persons (Abe, 1985;Cook, 1985). In this respect it differs not only from most modern-day Western conceptions of selfhood, but also from the egocentric, anthropocentric, substantial conceptions of the self of his time (Suzuki, 1949). As Cook (1985) concludes in his in-depth study of Dogen's view of authentic selfhood: "Dogen's relevance to the present times lies in the challenge he presents to naive and unexamined assumptions concerning what a self is" (p. 132f). Many Zen writers have stressed that one could get lost in one's superficial selfhood: "The apperceiving mind is where we form the notion of selfhood, and when this notion forgets the fact that its very existence is backed by no-mind-ness, personal egoism is asserted" (Suzuki, 1972, p. 143f.). To go beyond the personal egoism of one's superficial self involves a process of transcendence. As in the case of philosophical counseling, we may see this transcendence not only in terms of the aim of going beyond the self, but also in terms of the methods which seek to leap beyond the psychological level of existence without meddling with, or manipulating it. The Zen way is not to dwell on these psychological factors and their personal sources and manifestations. Rather it involves a turning away from these, it is through zazen-not through psychological introspection--that the individual goes beyond the psychological self. "The practice of Zen is body and mind casting off"(Hokyoki, trans.Waddell, p. 131). "Forgetting our feelings", not analyzing their origin is the way to transcendence. (Chan, 1963 p. 428) Dogen instructs his students to devote themselves fully to zazen: 'If you just harmonize your minds at first it will be easy to cast aside both your bodies and the world (Shobogenzo Zuimonki, trans. Masunaga, 1978, p. 27). Or in the words of Sekiso: "When a state of perfect motionlessness and unawareness is obtained all the signs of life will depart and also every trace of limitation will vanish... There is but one straight passage open and unobstructed through and P.289 through"(Suzuki, 1983, p.47). The history of Zen Buddhism is a testimony to the fact that transcendence is indeed possible through this "straight passage". Many have transcended their psychological needs and desires and attained enlightenment without psychological understanding. That is, one's true selfhood can be attained without the individual delving into personal psychological causes of, and reasons for his specific cravings, attachments, fears, etc. Pure Zen practice sufficed. But should this be a lesson for philosophical counseling regarding its potential to facilitate transcendence? CAN PHILOSOPHICAL COUNSELING LEAD TO SELF-TRANSCENDENCE? There is no doubt that philosophical self-examination has led to selftranscendence. We noted Tolstoy as evidence of this. But he, of course, is not the only one. Kierkegaard and some other great writers have revealed how their philosophical encounters and self-reflections were intimately tied to deep changes and transformations in their way of being. One may, however, argue that these were exceptional individuals. The question remains whether those individuals who come to seek counseling are also able to attain such transcendence through the guidance that they can receive in philosophical counseling. In briefly addressing this question here I will focus on the existence of psychological obstacles to change. Our philosophical life resides within a psychological substratum, and the latter may set limits on the possibility of our philosophical development. Would it not then be necessary to directly modify the psychological in order to facilitate the philosophical? Would awareness of the psychological influences be required? As we have seen, such direct psychological modification and awareness have been considered unnecessary in Zen. In part, the answer to this question will have to await the accumulation of a literature of philosophical counseling case and outcome studies. It is important to be aware, however, that this literature would have to provide information not only on the degree to which philosophical coun- P.290 seling has allowed the individual to overcome his psychological tendencies, but also to provide information regarding the obstacles to such overcoming in those individuals whose psychology continued to pull them in ways contradictory to the ones they chose on the basis of their philosophical understanding. Perhaps those whose psychological tendencies notably interfere would benefit from some psychological understanding for the release necessary to then proceed along their chosen path. It may further be wondered whether this path would not be applicable to those who fail to transcend through Zen practice as well. While many may have attained their true Buddha nature through purely traditional Zen practice, we must inquire into whether more can be done for those who did not attain this, whether those who failed could not have cleared away the psychological obstacles that lie in their path to transcendence through some kind of psychological treatment. While we await the accumulation of sufficient data, we may allow ourselves some speculation based on an understanding of the nature of philosophical counseling. It is clear that philosophical counseling does not offer the counselee the same optimal conditions for a drastic and comprehensive shift away from one's psychology that Zen offers. The counseling process does not provide affiliation, social order, community, or any other kind of supporting and guiding comprehensive framework. Nor does it offer or promise the individual a definite place into which to transcend, so to speak, analogous to the enlightened state promised in Zen. The counseling process also does not offer a specific type of truth. It does not point in a specific direction of transcendence, it does not clear a specific path along which the counselee can stride on his way to going beyond himself. While it does constitute a way of searching for the right way-through philosophical self understanding-the search is a lone one and there is no knowing where it will lead to. It would seem that under these circumstances, where the individual is left solely with his own philosophically informed will with which to face the psychological tendencies which he wishes to overcome, the potential influence of psychological tendencies is great relative to their influence on the Zen P.291 practitioner. Under such circumstances it may be necessary to integrate methods which operate directly on the individual's psychology. It should perhaps be noted here that these circumstances are not related to the nature of philosophy per se. In ancient Greece, where philosophy did offer both community and a specific truth, it would seem that psychological measures were not necessary. Without utilizing psychological analysis, the philosophies of that time had a profound impact on the life of the individual as well as on his transcendence (Hadot, 1995). DOES PSYCHOLOGICAL INTERVENTION INTERFERE WITH SELF-TRANSCENDENCE? While it may turn out to be necessary to integrate psychological methods into philosophical counseling if transcendence is to occur, we must examine whether from another direction such integration would not impede the philosophical process of transcendence. Elsewhere (Blass, 1994, in press)I have described how one can relate to the individual's psychology without necessarily viewing the individual's selfhood in terms of psychological mechanisms. In principle, then, it is possible to relate to the individual's psychological processes and take them into account, while seeing the essence of his selfhood in terms of, say, Zen or philosophical counseling. This does not, however, necessarily mean that in practice, focusing on a psychological understanding would not interfere with the maintenance of a philosophical counseling stance. Clearly, the nature of thinking involved in psychoanalysis is not of the kind that would be conducive, at the moment of its occurrence, to the state of mind sought through Zen. One cannot maintain a Zen-type attitude while also introspecting psychoanalytically. It would seem, in fact, to be quite the opposite. Psychoanalysis zooms in on just those things that Zen wishes to forget and cast off. But does this apply to philosophical counseling too? Does a psychological kind of thinking and experiencing oppose the process of philosophical counseling? This is a very difficult question. On the one hand, psychological P.292 exploration and understanding, while clearly different from those of philosophy (despite some overlap), are not alien to them. To be sure, they involve the application of a different body of knowledge and require thinking in terms of personal causes rather than in terms of conceptual connections and similar philosophical manners of thought, they involve a search for the psychological sources of the person's assumptions rather than an examination of their tenability or their logical implications they would not regard incoherence as an impetus to a better formulation, but to an understanding of its underlying causes, e.g., understanding of the conflictual ideas that are responsible for the incoherence. Nevertheless, despite these differences, the two do not appear to be incommensurable. It would appear that the temporary shift from a philosophical to a psychological kind of thought would not limit the individual's ability to then direct his thoughts back for further philosophical exploration. That is, given the individual's choice to view himself philosophically and accordingly to embark on a process of self-understanding of a philosophical kind, one could view the turn to psychology as a kind of releasing process that would then allow the individual to be more free and open to philosophical thinking and especially to the application of that thinking to one's life. In contrast, shifting back and forth between contradictory perspectives, as in the case of Zen and psychological exploration, would seem to be more complicated, although there still remains the possibility that for some people there would be no choice. Perhaps it would be for those of whom Dogen says: "You may say that you understand but still cannot give up certain things and practice zazen while holding on to various attachments. If you take this attitude you sink into delusion" (Shobogenzo Zuimonki, trans. Masunaga, 1978, p.8). For those who "still cannot give up certain things", psychological understanding of their childhood, or of their current needs and motivations that underlie these attachments may be the way to overcome them and to continue toward enlightenment rather than falling into delusion. On the other hand, there are potential dangers associated with the shift from a philosophical to a psychological encounter with the individual. P.293 The focus on psychological motivations and needs is a source of perpetual doubt of the truth of one's stance in the world. When one searches for psychological explanations of one's conceptions, there is a tendency to question the reasons for their appearance, their authenticity, and consequently their validity. While there may be value to this doubt, it may impede the development of certain ingredients that are very important to the philosophical process of transcendence. I refer here to two ingredients. One is faith in one's potential to come in touch with some truth, in the possibility of encountering (an aspect of) a reality that is not merely a solipsistic product of one's inner psychology. If an individual having an elusive contact with such faith is suddenly immersed in psychological doubt, it is possible that that important contact would be lost. The other ingredient is a kind of silence. In order to transcend oneself one must be attuned to the sound that comes from beyond, the guiding sound that comes from the whole of reality, as Jaspers put it. But if the noise of inner doubt is overbearing then our ears may be deafened. The focus on psychological motivations and needs may not only deafen us, but may also blind us, blind us to what lies outside of our psychological selves. Psychological introspection is indeed that-a turn of one's glance inwards, inwards to one's needs, desires, wishes, sensitivities, jealousies, etc. There is the possibility that this inwards glance would come at the expense of looking beyond ourselves, of turning to the Other, of turning to Being. It is not clear that the mere awareness that one's ultimate aim is self-transcendence is sufficient to counteract the pull of the inwardly-directed psychological perspective, and keep one on the path of the philosophical quest. Ultimately, it is perhaps with awareness of the dangers to the philosophical quest that psychological measures could,and maybe even should, be integrated. The self-doubt and self-focusedness that psychological awareness brings about-while being potential threats to one's tie to the beyond-are also potential safeguards against living in a philosophical world which is detached from one's actual life. They prevent living in a world of ideas that does not authentically reflect the way in which one P.294 relates to the Other, or to whatever lies beyond oneself. An example of this would be an individual living in a conceptual world governed by ideas of the unity of Being, unaware of the fact that his relationships to others are actually governed by self-concern. Focusing on one's motives and needs and recognizing them for what they are, as well as questioning and doubting oneself psychologically, may be a source of humble awareness to how one is actually standing in the world. It may allow the individual to see how he is not fully living what he believes to be his conceptual world. It may then also assist by clearing away the psychological impediments to living that world. Thus despite its dangers, psychological awareness may also serve as a means of protection against transcendence in bad faith. CONCLUSION To assist an individual in his path toward transcendence is a great and difficult task. It will lake time before philosophical counseling finds the best way to attain this aim. As it works toward the development of its own unique framework, both theoretical and practical, philosophical awareness and change. Further comparison of where this new field stands in relation to other more ancient traditions which aim at transcendence, such as Zen,would also be valuable. NOTES 1. See Blass, in press, for further elaboration of the distinction between the self as a psychological entity and the self as a philosophical one. 2. This view of man transcending himself in order to become man throug a philosophical listening to reality should not be confused with Sartre's view of transcendence. For Sartre, transcendence is a process whereby man creates himself-"Existence precedes essence". Gabriel Marcel, criticizes this misuse of the term transcendence. "Transcendence", he argues, cannot merely mean "going beyond", but rather must stand in opposition to immanence. (Marcel, 1969, p.48). Sartre's transcendence does not take man beyond the immanent, does not lead man beyond himself, and thus in many ways remains diametrically opposed to the position of Jaspers, Marcel, and the transcendent conception of philosophical counseling. REFERENCES Abe, M. (1985). The oneness of practice and attainment: Implications for the relations between means and ends. In, W.R.. Lafleur (ed.), Dogen Studies. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Achenbach, G.B. (1984). Philosophische Praxis, Koln: Jurgen Dinter. Achenbach, G.B. (1995). Philosophy, philosophical practice, and psychotherapy. In R. Lahav & M. Tillmans (eds.) Essays in Philosophical Counseling, pp. 61-74. Blass, R B. (1994). The concept of person in philosophical counseling and in psychotherapy: Can the two be integrated? Read at the First International Conference on Philosophical Counseling. The University of British Columbia, July, 1994. Blass, R B. (in press). The "person" in philosophical counseling vs. psychotherapy and the possibility of interchange between the fields. Journal of Applied Philosophy. Chan, W. (1963). A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Cohen, E.D. (1995) Philosophical counseling: some roles of critical thinking. In R. Lahav & M. Tillmans (eds.) Essays in Philosophical Counseling, pp. 121-131. Cook, F.H. (1985). Dogen's view of authentic selfhood and its socio-ehical implications. In W.R. Lafleur (ed.), Dogen Studies. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Fromm, E. (1950). Psychoanalysis and Religion. New Haven: Yale University Press. Hadot, P. (1995). Philosophy as a Way of Life. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Jaspers, K. (1954). The Way to Wisdom. New Haven: Yale University Press. Lahav,R. (1993). Using analytic philosophy in philosophical counseling. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 10:93-101. Lahav,R. (1994). Philosophical personal investigation in philosophical counseling. Read at the First International Conference on Philosophical Counseling, The University of British Columbia, July, 1994. Lahav,R. (1995a). A conceptual framework for philosophical counseling: world-view interpretation. In R. Lahav & M. Tillmans (eds.) Essays in Philosophical Counseling,pp. 3-24. Lahav,R. (1995b). We have hardly the beginning if anything at all. (Michael Schefczyk interviewing Ran Lahav) . Zeitschrift fur Philosophische Praxis, 2/95,pp. 4-7. Lahav,R. (In press) What is philosophical in philosophical counseling? Journal of Applied Philosophy. Lahav,R. (this volume). Philosophical counseling and Taoism: Wisdom and lived philosophical understanding. The Journal of Chinese Philosophy. Lahav,R. & Tillmans,M. (eds.)(1995). Essays in Philosophical Counseling. Lanham: University Press of America. Lindseth,A. (1990). Was ist Philosophische Praxis? Agora, 8/9: 12-15. Marcel,G (1969). The Mystery of Being. Chicago: Gateway Edition. Masunaga,R. (1978). A Primer of Soto Zen A translation of Shobogenzo Zumonki.. Honolulu: The University Press of Hawaii. Norman, B. (1995). Philosophical counseling: the arts of ecological relationship and interpretation In R.Lahav & M. Tillmans (eds.) Essays in Philosophical Counseling, pp.49-58. Schefczyk, M. (1994). Philosohical counseling as a critical examination of life-directing conceptions. Read at the First International Conference on Philosophical Counseling, The University of British Columbia, July, 1994. Segal,S. (1995). Meaning crisis: philosophical counseling and psychotherapy. In R. Lahav & M. Tillmans (eds.) Essays in Philosophical Counseling, pp. 101-119. Suzuki,D.T.(1949). Essays in Zen Buddhism. London: Rider & Co. Suzuki,D.T. (1972). The Zen Doctrine of No-Mind. York Beach: Samuel Weiser Inc. Suzuki,D.T. (1983). An Introduction to Zen Buddhism. London: Rider. P.297 Tillmans,M.L.A. (1994). Philosophical counseling: The art of hearing through experience. Inquiry: Critical thinking across the disciplines 13, 3-8. Veening, E. (1994). Metalogue in philosophical counseling. Read at the First International Conference on Philosophical Counseling, The University of British Columbia, July, 1994. Waddell, N.A. (trans.) Hokyoki, In The Eastern Buddhist, 10(2).