Existential and Ontological Dimensions of Time in Heidegger

and Dogen by Steven Heine
STEVE ODIN
JOURNAL OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY 14 (1987)
pp.249-257
COPYYRIHGT @ 1987 BY DIALOGUE PUBLISHING COMPANY, HONOLULU,
HAWAII, U.S.A.


. p.249 Existential and Ontological Dimensions of Time in Heidegger and Dogen by Steven Heine is an excellent new study which makes a significant contribution to our understanding of Japanese Buddhism and EastWest comparative philosophy. Grounded in the original German language edition of Heidegger's Sein und Zeit (Being and Time) as well as the Japanese language edition of Dogen's Shobogenzo(a) (Treasury of the True Dharma-Eye) , Heine's work goes far in successfully realizing its stated aim of establishing a "framework for philosophical dialogue between Heidegger and Dogen through an examination of their analyses of the true nature, structure and meaning of time in terms of a convergence of existential and ontological dimensions." (p. ix) The inclusion of a new annotated translation of the Uji(b) or "Being-Time" chapter of Dogen's Shobogenzo further adds to the value of Heine's book. Heine argues that Heidegger and Dogen are uniquely suited for critical comparative and cross-cultural study not only because both attempt to overcome the deficiencies of their respective philosophical traditions on the subject of time, but also insofar as both thinkers "reorient our understanding of all phases of existence and experience in terms of time and temporality,death and dying,finitude and impermanence..." (p. ix) In Chapter 1 of his work entitled "The Question of Time" he cites Heidegger's assertion that "our treatment of the meaning of Being must enable us to show that the central problematic of all ontology is rooted in the phenomenon of time..." (p. 14) This fundamental inseparability of being and time established by Heidegger's work Sein and Zeit is then related to Dogen's famous Zen Buddhist doctrine of uji or "being-time." In this context Heine cites Dogen's proclamation from the "Uji" chapter P.250 of his Shobogenzo which states: "time itself (ji) already is none other than being(s) (u); and being(s) are all none other than time." (p. 28) In Chapter 2 entitled "The Origin of Derivative Time" Heine analyzes the attempted overcoming of derivative time in the thought of both Heidegger and Dogen. Heine develops Heidegger's analysis accord to which Being in its primordial sense of "presencing" (Anwesenheit) becomes reduced to the objectified status of a substantial entity (ousia). (p. 36) As Heine points out, for Heidegger the "inauthentic" (uneigentlich) mode of existence is a state of "falling" (Verfallen) in which Dasein is preoccupied with the present. (p. 61) In falling, everything primordial and mysterious is considered obvious and self-evident, and the dynamism of primordial temporality is reduced to mere derivate time or clock-time conceived as a series of static now-points.(p. 42) According to Heidegger's critique of Western philosophy from Plato to Nietzsche, it is this derivative notion of time as a succession of substantial "nows" based on an inauthentic preoccupation with the present which generates false conceptions of eternalism. Heine next relates Heidegger's critique of derivative time to Dogen's criticism of what Japanese Buddhism terms sennigedo(c) or the "Senika heresy," which refers to the false eternalization and substantialization of mujo-bussho(d) or "impermanence- Buddha-nature." Heine writes: "In 'Bussho' Dogen exposes a variety of misconceptions permeating Mahayana and Zen theories and practices that stem from fundamentally derivative views of being-time. Buddha-nature, he suggests, is frequently posited as an eternal substance which is actual yet transcendent of moral causation and the life-death process..." (p. 58) In Chapter 3 entitled "Finitude and Impermance" Heine analyzes how notions of derivative time are finally overcome through the disclosure of radical contingency pervading all existence, revealed in terms of Heidegger's notion of "finitude" (Endlichkeit) and Dogen's interpretation of "impermanence" (mujo(e)). Heine asserts: The notion of finitude in Heidegger's understanding of Being and the interpretion of impermanence in Dogen's approach to Zen have a parallel role for each thinker's project in terms of overcoming fixations with substance and attachments to p.251 eternalism, and in establishing the basis for a realization of the dynamism, unity and insubstantiality of primordial time. (p.71) Heine further argues that although Heidegger's notion of finitude and Dogen's idea of impermanence are quite distinct in terms of many of the conclusions drawn by each thinker, both concepts function similarly insofar as they point to the radical contingency of existence, ontologically revealed through "nothingness" which pervades man's existential encounters with vicissitude, anxiety, dying and loss. (p. 71) In the case of Heidegger, Heine asserts that Dasein's "authentic" (eigentlich) existence as a Being-in-time is the ontological-temporal bails for its"existenzial disclosure of finitude as Being-thrown-unto-death or Being-towards-the-end." (p. 74) At this point Heine relates Heidegger's notion of authentic finite existence as Being-in-time and Being-towards-death to the Zen Buddhist thought of Dogen, which maintains that 'the fundamental significance of impermanence is directly and inseparably related to an ontological/existential realization of the Buddhist truth of non-self (muga, (f) the thoroughgoing insubstantiality of human and phenomenal existence)." (p. 75) Thus Heine concludes: "Heidegger and Dogen share a concentration on death and dying as the extreme experiential point for the convergence of the dimensions of existential decision and ontological disclosure concerning radical contingency," adding that "death penetrates every moment of and aspect of life, so that the ways one encounters his dying becomes normative for his approach toward living." (p. 97) Finally, in Chapter 4 entitled "Primordial Time" Heine describes the dynamic existential and ontological unity of non-substantive temporality as developed by Heidegger in terms of his notion of "primordial time" (ursprugliche Zeit) and by Dogen in terms of what he calls the "truth of being-time" (uji no dori(g)). At the outset of this chapter Heine writes: The aim of the exposition of primoridal time by Heidegger and Dogen is to show that true temporality...is fundamentally and essentially interrelated with and inseparable from existence." (p. 105) Throughout this chapter, Heine not only emphasizes the inseparability of being and time, but also the total dynamism, unity and nonsubstantiality of pri- p.252 mordial time for both Heidegger and Dogen. Moreover, he emphasizes that by means of their respective notions of primordial time, both Heidegger and Dogen attempt a radical overcoming of substance and eternalist ontology derived from linear now-time. However, at this point Heine sharply distinguished the positions of these two thinkers. He repeatedly argues that for Heidegger, primordial and authentic time is futural, based on the resolute "anticipation" of one's projected possibilities; Dasein's fallenness is always associated with the present. Although Dogen refutes the "now" that has been isolated from existence and from past and future, he ultimately affirms the simultaneity of all three tenses within the here-and-now of each dynamic and totalistic moment based on the experience of genjokoan(h) or "the immediate and complete manifestation of Zen realization." (pp. 31, 137, 140, 143) On this basis, Heine further argues: "Thus the central existential difference between Heidegger and Dogen is that Dogen insists that the True Man must not await, expect or anticipate the arrival of the presencing of time because he penetrates insubstantiality here-and-now." (p. 141) Although Heine's book succeeds well in its aim at establishing a framework for philosophical dialogue between Heidegger and Dogen on the problem of time, many scholars might seriously question the balance and neutrality of his dialogue. For in fact, Heine repeatedly employs the Zen Buddhist thought of Dogen as a standpoint from which to criticize the limitations of Heidegger's philosophy of time. For instance, he writes: It will be shown that whereas Heidegger's analysis of now-time leads to an emphasis on the priority of future and past and to an inability to disclose the temporality of entities, Dogen overcomes the inauthentic static now-point through disclosure of the all-inclusive simultaneous passage (kyoryaku) of the three tenses encompassing all phenomena. (p. 36) However, some would no doubt argue that Heidegger's account has not failed to disclose the temporality of existence, but has in fact brilliantly described the dynamic interplay of all three tenses in the continuity of primordial time while yet carefully distinguishing the unique phenome- p.253 nological characteristics of each tense in a way not sufficiently articulated in Dogen's analysis. Thus, in order to balance his discussion it seems incumbent upon Heine to consider how one might also criticize Dogen from the standpoint of Heidegger's analysis. Perhaps my most serious criticism of Heine's analysis is that although it provides an excellent description of the "continuity" central to Dogen's idea of uji or "being-time," it completely fails to underscore the radical discontinuity which this theory also involves. In his account of Dogen's theory of being-time Heine emphasizes that the immediate experience of nikon(i) or "right here-and-now" does not give rise to the Senika heresy of eternalizing Buddha-nature or substantializing the 'now" since it is counter-balanced by the notion of kyoryaku(j) -comprehended as "totalistic passage" in the sense of "experiential continuity." In Heine's words: "Dogen further avoids any confusion of nikon with a newly derivative eternalism by stressing the temporal depth and experiential breath of the right-now in terms of the notion of experiential continuity or totalistic passage (kyoryaku)." (p. 129) Elsewhere in his text, Heine refers to this notion of kyoryaku or "experiential continuity" as denoting the idea of "continuous passage" (p.127) or the "continuity of time" (p.181). Along with the consciousness of nikon or "right here-and-now," it is this awareness of kyoryaku or "continuous passage" which constitutes the primordial experience of being-time according to Heine's analysis of Dogen. Although Heine's explication of being-time in terms of what herms of what he calls "the dual notions of nikon and kyoryaku" (p.143) is in itself illuminating, it wholly neglects the radical discontinuity which many scholars regard as primary in Dogen's concept of mujo or impermanence and uji or being-time. For instance, in his work entitled Dogen Kigen-Mystical Realist, Hee-jin Kim emphasizes that there is an 'ultimacy of discontinuity" in Dogen's Zen Buddhist theory of being-time.(1) As Kim explains, for Dogen each discontinuous "dharma-position" (ju-hoi(k)) constitutes the whole of "being-time" (uji) as an "absolute now" (nikon), comprehended as the self-actualization of the total presence of the Buddha-nature. Kim further elaborates: p.254 This is a radical rejection of the flow of time, or the stream of consciousness, or any other conception of time based on the idea of continuity or duration. That is, time is absolutely discrete and discontinuous. This characteristic is primary in Dogen's thought.(2) Moreover, this "ultimacy of discontinuity" at the base of Dogen's Zen Buddhist thought further raises a question as to the adequacy of a Heideggerean interpretation of uji or being-time. For in fact, Heidegger phenomenologically describes primordial time as being purely "ecstatic" (ek- static) and "continuous" (kontinuierlich) . Accordingly, throughout his analysis of Heidegger's thought, Heine repeatedly emphasizes this uninterrupted "continuity" (Kontinuitat) or "ecstatic-horizonal" unity of primordial time along with the undivided "continuity of Dasein." (pp. 116-118) To give just one example, Heine states: "Temporality is the ekstatikon pure and simple by whith Dasein views itself as temporalhistorical unity and individualized continuity of finite transcendence, rather than as a collection of isolated yet serially connected time units." (pp. 116-17) Yet, neither in Heidegger nor in Heine's account of Heidegger can one discover anything comparable to the "ultimacy of discontinuity" in Dogen's theory of being-time. In a chapter of his book Zen and Western Thought entitled "Dogen on Buddha-Nature," Abe Masao also emphasizes this radical discontinuity of being-time in Dogen's theory of mujo-bussho or "impermanenceBuddha-nature," writing: "Dogen denies continuity of time and emphasizes the independence of each point of time... "(3) He adds: "Only by the realization of the complete discontinuity of time and of the independent moment... does time become real time."(4) Yet, in Dogen's concept of uji or being-time, primordial temporality is not merely discontinuous, since it also flows continuously as is denoted by the concept of kyoryaku (continuous passage). For this reason Abe further asserts: "However, in spite of the complete discontinuity of time and independent moment, time flows. This is kyoryaku, i.e., seriatim passage..."(5) Hence, for Dogen there is a profound sense in which being-time is both discontinuous and continuous. In this context,I would argue p.255 that Dogen's theory of being-time is best comprehended from the stand-point of Japan's foremost 20th century speculative philosopher Nishida Kitaro (1870-1945), who argues that the unity of time is itself a "continuity of discontinuity" (hirenzoku no renzoku) .(1) Thus, in his work entitled Tetsugaku no kompon mondai.(Fundamental Problems of Philo- sophy)Nishida writes: As I have said before, the unity of the individual cannot be thought of as simply a continuity, rather, it must be a continuity of discontinuity, so as to constitute the unity of independent beings with every step. Each moment of time passes into the next moment by negating itself, hence establishing the unity of time.(6) Nishida specifically refutes the position held by conventional Western substance philosophy which conceives of time as a series of discrete now-points, i.e., as a mere "discontinuity" (hirenzoku(m)),yet, he also repudiates the concept of time as pure duration or "continuity" (renzoku(n)) as held by such philosophers as Bergson, Husserl or Heidegger. Instead, the unity of time constituting the true self can only be described as a "discontinuous continuity," or as it were, a "continuity of discontinuity." From this perspective Nishida further argues that the discontinuous continuity of temporal experience results in a heightened existential awareness of death and nothingness at every moment: "For the individual to be connected to the following moment as the continuity of discontinuity it is necessary that one die at this moment and enter into nothingness."(7) In the West, this Japanese Buddhist view of primoridal time as discontinuous continuity has received its clearest articulation by the process thought of Alfred North Whitehead. In his earliest philosophical text entitled An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge Whitehead, like Heidegger, rigorously protests against the standpoint of conventional substance philosophy and scientific materialism which regards time as a series of discrete now-points, arguing that "we do not perceive isolated facts,but a continuity of existence."(8) However,in a p.256 later work entitled Science and the Modern World, Whitehead makes a radical shift from temporal continuity to "temporal atomicity," now arguing that the notion of "discontinuous existence"(9) introduced by recent quantum theory has prompted him to completely revise his description of physical reality. Whitehead's so-called "epochal" theory of time as a discontinuous continuity finally culminates in Process and Reality, wherein he argues that due to the discontinuity or quantum characteristic of each becoming and perishing occasion, temporal passage involves not a "continuity of becoming," but a "becoming of continuity."(10) In other words, there is a new "creation of continuity" within each discontinuous occasion of temporal experience. Moreover, for Whitehead this discontinuous continuity of temporal passage is the basis for an existential awareness of death at every moment, namely, a tragic sense of time as "perpetually perishing."(11) For this reason I would argue that Whitehead's process cosmology provides what is possibly the most adequate Western categoreal scheme by which to cognize the theory of time as a "continuity of discontinuity" developed by both Dogen and Nishida in Japan. Indeed, in a footnote Heine himself remarks that "Whiteheadian process philosophy of the harmonious and dynamic universe of prehensive events and developing organisms perhaps poses a significant challenge to Heidegger's Dasein-oriented approach to the question of time." (p. 164) In this context, I have considered the extent to which Whitehead's process thought provides a serious alternative to Heidegger's philosophy as a Western hermeneutic capable of interpreting Dogen's theory of uji or being-time in Japanese Zen Buddhism. Nonetheless, Heine's work Existential and Ontological Dimensions of Time in Heidegger and Dogen makes an important advance towards formulating a cross-cultural framework aimed at overcoming all substance and eternalist ontology derived from static now-time, while also establishing a basis for the dynamism,unity and nonsubstantiality of primordial time. On this basis, Heine's book can be strongly recommended to anyone interested in the fields of Japanese Buddhism, Heidegger's existentialism or East-West comparative studies. p.257 NOTES 1. Hee-Jin Kim, Dogen Kigen-Mystical Realist (Tucson, Arizona: The University of Arizona Press, 1975), p.213. 2. Ibid, p.202. 3. Masao Abe, Zen and Western Thought, ed. W.R.LaFIeur (Honolulu: University of Hawaii press, 1985). See Chapter 2 entitled Dogen on Buddha Nature," p.63. 4. Ibid., p.64. 5. Ibid., p.65. 6. Kitaro Nishida, Tetsugaku no kompon mondai (Fundamental Problems of philosophy) from Nishida Kitaro Zenshu (The complete Works of Nishida Kitaro), 10 vols. (2nd ed., Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1965), vol.VII, p.268. 7. Ibid., p.295. 8. Alfred North Whitehead, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1919; second edition, 1924), pp.7-8. 9. Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World (New York: Macmillan, second edition, The Free press, 1967), p.135. 10. Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality (New York: Macmillan. 1929 corrected edition, ed. by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. The Free press, 1978), p. 35. 11. Ibid, p. 340. For Whitehead, as for NIshida Kitaro, this "discontinuity" of all microcosmic-macrocosmic quantum events is crucial not only for its radical existential implications, but also because it is the ground of creativity, novelty and freedom in each becoming and perishing occasion of temporal experience. GLOSSARY OF JAPANESE TERMS a 正法眼藏 h 現成公案 b 有時 i 而今 c 先尼外道 j 經歷 d 無常佛性 k 住法位 e 無常 l 非連續ソ連續 f 無我 m 非連續 g 有時ソ道理 n 連續