Religion And Moral Meaning In Bioethics

C.S Campbell

Hastings Cent Rep

Vol.20 No. 4 Jul-Aug.1990

Pp.4-10

Copyright by Hastings Cent Rep


RELIGION AND MORAL MEANING IN BIOETHICS Few experiences in life seem more pointless, more suggestive that our lives are subject to powers that are arbitrary, abusive, and destructive, than the suffering and death of children. What possible account could be given to explain, let alone give meaning to such an event? Several years ago, I developed a friendship with a young couple who were anxiously awaiting the birth of their first child. What transpired, quite unexpectedly, was every prospective parent's nightmare their child was born with serious congenital abnormalities, evidenced visibly by facial disfigurement and substantial respiratory difficulties. Following a short stay in an NICU, the neonatologists indicated that though they could not be sure when death would occur, they were certain that the child's prognosis was terminal, and asked the parents for their preferences regarding continuing or stopping treatment. How might we think about such a problem in contemporary bioethics? We might invoke a benefits versus burdens calculation or a best interests standard, or take procedural recourse to an ethics committee, perhaps recommending withdrawal of life support. Or, we might consider the cogency of arguments supporting active killing as a compassionate act to spare the child what would inevitably be a painful life, whatever its duration. But the parents did not ask those kinds of questions; they instead brought to that very difficult situation an understanding that our lives are subject to ultimate powers which are creative, nurturing, and redeeming, and a way of construing the world shaped decisively by a set of religious convictions about the purpose of life, the meaning of death, and ultimate human destiny. Within that moral vision, Angela was not seen by her parents as a tragedy to be prevented (by prenatal diagnosis and abortion) or an unwanted burden whose life could easily be shortened, but instead as a girl in need of care. With minimal medical support, my friends took Angela home to begin their family life bound together, and over the next few months gave devoted and unceasing care until she died. I do not relate this story to say the parents' choice to care for their daughter at home rather than let her die in the hospital was ethically tight or justifiable. I am still unsure about that choice, even though the subsequent care Angela received was to me an exemplary witness of how we should collectively treat the vulnerable and voiceless in our midst. Rather, my point is that a world view provided meaning in a situation that seemed pervaded by arbitrariness and cruelty, a meaning that could not be supplied or sustained by our conventional bioethics maxims about "best interests" or "substituted judgment." The tragedy seen by others, including myself, was transformed into a girl. "Suffer the little children... for of such is the kingdom of God." Religion offers an interpretation or revelation of reality that responds to what Max Weber referred to as the "metaphysical needs of the human mind" to seek order, coherence, and meaning in our lives, to understand ultimate questions about our nature, purpose, and destiny. Yet, in our common endeavor to do bioethics within the limits of reason alone, the discourse necessary to sustain the traditions of moral insight and meaning embedded in the practices and values of religious communities may be characterized as "private" and so considered largely irrelevant to the overriding objectives of bioethics. Indeed, prominent scholars have given serious consideration to whether traditions of theological ethics may constructively contribute to bioethics and to the practices of health care, and the conclusion on several accounts may often be that such a moral resource is dispensable "Bioethics, where it succeeds, shows where it does not need theology."(n1) The tensions between religious discourse and bioethics pose dual challenges of accessibility and meaning. Insofar as the incorporation of moral claims from a specific religious tradition or community is deemed to undermine the possibilities for a generally accessible bioethics discourse, the significance of religious perspectives may be very limited. Yet the criterion of accessibility may limit the moral richness of bioethics, for the costs of conformity to public discourse requirements may be the loss of meaning and content about ultimate concerns embedded in a particular tradition, whether religious (as illustrated by the story of Angela's parents) or professional (for example, medicine or nursing). The Public Limits of Religious Discourse If it was premature to pronounce "the death of God" in the 1960s, it seems equally mistaken to begin doing post-mortems on the demise of theological and religious perspectives in bioethics. There are nevertheless several problems posed for religious thinkers by the criterion of a generally accessible bioethics discourse, as succinctly identified by Leon Kass: Perhaps for the sake of getting a broader hearing, perhaps not to profane sacred teachings or to preserve a separation between the things of God and the things of Caesar, most religious ethicists entering the public practice of ethics leave their special insights at the door and talk about "deontological vs. consequentialist," "autonomy vs. paternalism," "justice vs. utility," just like everybody else.(n2) A first limit on religious discourse in bioethics, then, has to do with constructing a moral language appropriate to an interdisciplinary and public audience. Religious thinkers no longer converse only with members of a particular religious community affirming a common set of assumptions. The audience of bioethics is instead comprised of a broad range of academics and professionals, who likely do not share the same moral, let alone theological, language and concepts. In this setting, the substantive but private insights of a particular tradition may need to be translated into concepts that have public significance. The linguistic compromises required to gain a "broader heating," however, risk substantive compromises, since the common discourse of bioethics may not be sufficiently rich to convey the full meaning of relevant religious language. For example, the biblical concept of the "image of God" expresses a transcendent and relational understanding of the self that may be diminished by proposed equivalents of "personhood" or "autonomy," while both the motivational and substantive elements of "covenant" seem only minimally conveyed by the language of "contract." Moreover, though the principle of "beneficence" may be in the bioethics lexicon, even at its most morally demanding it is a very diluted form of "neighbor-love." The problem of translating religious discourse into a common bioethics language, without attenuating or transforming its meaning, has for some religious thinkers illustrated the potential for cooptation involved in addressing a secular world on its terms and in its concepts. Rather than "profane sacred teachings" as Kass puts it, the alternative to this perceived compromise may be to affirm an ethic of an exemplary community that witnesses to the integrity of its religious convictions primarily in practice rather than discourse. Stanley Hauerwas, for example, has maintained that appreciating "the integrity of Christian discourse--[entails] that Christian beliefs do not need translation but should be demonstrated through Christian practices...."(n3) There is, to be sure, an important vocational reason for retaining the integrity of religious discourse. Unlike moral philosophers, for example, theologians do have a particular audience or constituency to whom they are accountable, namely, their various religious communities, whose historical traditions of reflection may be inadequate for the new questions of practical ethics raised by contemporary biotechnology and medicine. Part of the theological concern with addressing a public audience on generally accessible grounds, then, is that it may compromise not only a vocational responsibility to speak out of a particular religious tradition, but also a responsibility to speak to the tradition embodied in an identifiable community of believers. Yet a third consideration to which Kass alludes is the church-state controversy, or the societal interest in preserving a wall of separation between religious and public concerns. This limit may be particularly significant in those settings where a specific kind of public bioethics is required--the articulation of public or institutional policy by advisory commissions or committees. The institutionalization of bioethics can reinforce the necessity for a generally accessible language, not only to facilitate ethical discourse among members of such commissions, but also so that they can explain and defend their recommendations to the public on grounds accessible to all. In the process of public policymaking on bioethics issues, for example, religious themes are typically acknowledged, either through the appointment of particular commission members as representatives of a certain tradition or in public hearings in which invited representatives from a tradition present position statements. These statements may at times articulate distinctive conclusions on the issues under consideration based on the moral reasoning of a religious tradition, as exemplified by the testimony opposing the use of human fetal tissue for purposes of transplantation by Roman Catholic and Jewish scholars presented to an NIH panel in 1988. In other instances, the arguments of religious traditions may be "essentially the same" as the conclusions supported by secular moral reasoning.(n4) Whatever the contributions of religious traditions to the policymaking process, given the particular constitutional configurations of our polity the outcomes and conclusions need to be articulated and defended publicly on nonreligious, generally accessible grounds. That is, the constitutional requirements of a secular purpose for legislation and the constitutional restrictions on appeals to religious grounds as authorization for legislation impose political limits on the scope of religious argumentation.(n5) The sense that the contributions of religious discourse to contemporary bioethics are limited by these interdisciplinary, theological, and political parameters assumes of course that religious traditions have something substantively distinctive to communicate to a public, secular audience. But where might we locate these distinctive or special insights? I want to suggest that the answers to the conventional bioethics questions of "who should decide?" or what should we do?" often--if we felt free to allow them to do so--would push back to fundamental issues that require a substantive account of the purpose of human life and destiny. These are common questions of meaning that religious communities have devoted considerable attention to in their theologies, rituals, and practical ethics. The Anomaly of Suffering The nature of the accessibility-meaning dichotomy can initially be illustrated by attending to some very contested questions in contemporary bioethics. Two examples will suffice. In an influential discussion of the moral status of animals, one philosopher explains his neglect of religious argumentation for the concept of the "sanctity of life" because such views do not provide "reasoned explanation." Moreover, even sanctity of life proponents typically appeal to nonreligious reasons, since "[religious] doctrines are no longer as widely accepted as they once were."(n6) Another has observed that religious arguments prohibiting active killing in medical practice have limited scope in the secular domain; even if one "eschews euthanasia on religious grounds, there will be the challenge of establishing in' general terms why a secular society compassing a plurality of moral viewpoints may forbid euthanasia."(n7) The constraints on religious discourse are in part its sociological inadequacy (because in our secular age purely religious appeals will not be sufficient for public moral reasoning), and in part its logical inadequacy (because the arational nature of such appeals will be unsatisfactory as a foundation for moral reasoning). For the sake of general accessibility, then, we may be tempted to do bioethics without recourse to important sources and traditions of meaning in our culture. Yet if we consider what is driving moral debate on both "animal rights" and euthanasia, we are likely to find what has historically been deemed a question of religious meaning right at the core, for it is difficult to discuss either of these issues without invoking the notion of "suffering." The central question in attributing moral status to animals, in Jeremy Bentham's classic formulation, is, "Can they suffer?," while arguments on euthanasia often turn on the availability of alternatives to "relieve suffering." Our moral disagreements in bioethics over whether animals should be used in research or over appropriate care of the dying may thus reflect not only (if at all) differences in moral norms, but also various understandings of the place and meaning of suffering in our lives. Even prior to its significance for such controversial issues, the concept of suffering seems central for the most fundamental concerns of bioethics. Suffering is in part constituted by the experience of a profound assault upon or threat to our sense of self and identity that we are unable to control. It is the experience of the inexplicably arbitrary and typically destructive, of what Weber referred to as the "ethical irrationality of the world." It is perhaps such a perception of illness and disease that lies behind the Latin root (pati) of our "patient," meaning "the one who suffers." Religious traditions do not have a monopoly on discourse about suffering, nor is there a univocal understanding of suffering common to all religions. It is nevertheless the case that the meaning of suffering has long been a central concern of much theological reflection and many religious communities. If such a concept is a central presupposition of both basic conceptual (what is a "patient"?) and controversial pragmatic problems in bioethics (the human treatment of animals), the traditions of religious discourse about suffering would seem to present a rich resource for substantive insights. Some conceptual comprehension of "necessary suffering" is needed, for example, to make sense of moral arguments, let alone current public referenda proposals in Oregon and Washington that would sanction active euthanasia in cases of "unnecessary" suffering. A Journey of Meaning Suffering is not of course an end of religious experience but a problem demanding interpretation. Religious traditions have historically tried to give meaning to suffering by placing the experience in a context of broader questions about ultimate purpose in life, and even human destiny beyond life. The "ethically irrational" is typically explained by the construction of a theodicy that reconciles the presence of evil and suffering within a concept of salvation. Inr' example, suffering may be descriptive of life within the cycle of karma. In some Western traditions, suffering has been construed as having punitive, pedagogical, or redemptive purposes in human experience, though the incompleteness of all such constructions is suggested by the paradigmatic biblical story of the suffering of Job and, in our time, by the experience of the Jews in the Holocaust. Whether suffering does have a "point" and what that point may be will vary among religious traditions. My claim, however, is that the moral intelligibility of suffering is dependent on some account, theological or philosophical, of human nature and ultimate human ends; any conception of bioethics, therefore, that purports to take suffering seriously will likewise have to consider such ultimate questions. The substantive responses of religious traditions to questions about our origins, who we are, what the nature and purpose of life is, and what constitutes our ultimate ends, account in part of course for the practical and moral differences among traditions. While acknowledging tiffs diversity and complexity, I want to illustrate, by drawing on one fairly common interpretation of lift in religious traditions, how such ultimate perspectives can present important implications for our models of bioethics. For many traditions, a fundamental metaphor for life is that of a journey or pilgrimage. The meaning of the journey is derived in part from its rebus, the promise of passage or deliverance, including deliverance from the ills and adversity encountered in life, and which also gives point and purpose to morality as the requirements of character and action necessary to transform the kind of people we are (human nature) into the kind of people we ought to be (human destiny). The life given to us by powers that are ultimately creating, sustaining, and redeeming is not without its thickets and thorns, yet it is precisely through the encounter with human (evil and sin) and natural (disease) forms of opposition that progress in the journey is possible, for such experiences shape decisively the identity and Character of the moral self. Thus participation in the journey is intrinsically valuable, a source of meaning through experience of oppression, adversity, and perhaps even suffering. That meaning is constructed and explained, clarified and communicated, in stories and narratives of creation, alienation, and reconciliation told to others and retold as part of an ongoing tradition. The journey is thus as well a communal experience that involves the making of covenants and promises, the mutual binding together of former strangers for common purposes and ends, through which moral responsibilities are mediated. This teleological account of human experience can reveal several features to us about the character of contemporary bioethics. It is part of our set of cultural assumptions that meaning is created (or not) by the autonomous individual. Consider, for example, how we understand our pervasive concern with "dying with dignity" in bioethics. A conventional explanation is that this involves returning to the patient control over his or her dying. But, as Kass has observed, it is far from clear that "dignity will reign only when we can push back officious doctors, machinery, and hospital administrators."(n8) Dignity must be informed by meaning, and it is perhaps the case that we will achieve dying with meaning only as we understand the place of death within a notion of a meaningful life. Moreover, within the vision of life as a journey, the hard cases, quandaries, and dramatic scenarios of bioethics are disclosed as but a time-slice in the narrative of a person's moral quest. A devotion to problem-solving both reflects and reinforces a cultural tendency to excise an individual from the social and temporal ties, from community and history, that present sources of meaning in the moral life. Accommodating questions of meaning in bioethics will require that we broaden its scope beyond our current fixation with problem-solving, for some problems cannot be solved but must still be faced. This broader vision involves directing attention not only to the means of medicine, such as procedures for obtaining informed consent or the regulation of research protocols, but also the purposes of medicine within the context of a life conceived as a journey. For on such an account, health will be valued not merely for its own sake, but for the ends it allows us to pursue, while sickness and illness may signify not only inconvenient interruptions, but also teachers whose meaning we share with others through stories. The journey metaphor, because it presupposes a conception of human ends, directly confronts us with questions about the moral pre-suppositions of a medicine wedded to technology and conquest of the endless frontier of scientific research. Formulating what these questions are, let alone answering them, is a task made more complex by the very successes of technological medicine, which may render prior, longstanding moral or religious concepts inadequate or in need of reinterpretation. For example, the suffering for generations associated with the experience of infertility--often reinforced culturally by religious worldviews--may now, through various technological interventions, be transformed into an instance of unnecessary suffering. Is suffering such an unmitigated evil, and its perduring presence such a concession to failure, that medicine ought, as many have argued, to aspire to its elimination? Or does suffering require the compassion of persons who embody the meaning of care? Such matters are particularly acute in debates over active euthanasia, where eliminating suffering involves eliminating the person who suffers. Yet a medicine that aspires to achieve such a purpose may conflict with specific religious perspectives that see suffering as less a problem to be solved than as an unavoidable part of one's journey, and which assumes meaning in the context of that journey. For example, Paul Ramsey once rhetorically inquired whether "the purpose of modem medicine is to relieve the human condition of the human condition," by which Ramsey had particularly in mind the illness, disease, and suffering all persons experience as their mortal lot. Such an objective not only commits medicine to an impossible task, but one that risks dehumanizing its practitioners and patients. To the extent that medicine is not morally bounded, or transforms conceptual boundaries, it may summon a theological critique essentially concerned with the theme of idolatry, of making of health an absolute, the end of the human journey, rather than a value whose meaning is intelligible only within some broader account of human nature and destiny. Such a critique will thus be directed against the assertion of an unbounded dominion expressed in some definitions of health, which threaten to transform every human problem into one that is or eventually can be susceptible to medical resolution, It is directed as well against pretensions to unbridled authority and control, and unlimited knowledge in the medical context, and against the well-intentioned aspiration to alleviate the common problems of the human condition in a way that is dehumanizing. Such pretensions and aspirations frequently converge in contemporary medicine's ongoing battle with the enemy of death. In a culture void of meaning, death must appear as the crowning surd. Its power in our culture is disclosed in the ways we seek to evade it. The vast majority of persons now die in alien environments, institutions such as hospitals and nursing homes, which shelter the living from personally confronting death and may isolate the dying from all that has comprised their journey, including, at times, their families. For the living, moreover, our culture increasingly holds out a promise of technological deliverance, through the medicine of resuscitation or organ transplantation, for example, together with empirical data on "the risk," factor--typically the probability of contracting a disease or developing a condition that has some statistically significant correlation with death--of almost every conceivable activity. We seek to evade this ultimate assault on the self and yet, as Camus's Dr. Rieux comments, it organizes our lives and medical activities. "The order of the world is shaped by death.(n9) The value of life conveyed in the journey metaphor likewise implies that religious traditions cannot (and do not) look upon death with indifference. Indeed, on some accounts, death may be perceived as the pervasive sign of the intruding presence of evil. Life is a fundamental, even if not an absolute, good; the tragedy that we ascribe particularly to premature or "untimely" death from illness or accident is in part attributable to a sense that a person's journey has been interrupted. Yet for all the shadows cast by death, we may also respond to it not as intruder but as deliverer from a completed mortal journey. That response underlies the interpretation of death as a "blessing" found in some traditions of religious ethics, often reflected in support for practices of only caring for the dying rather than prolonging life through unceasing technological support. The issue is not so much whether we can be delivered from death, either through relying on technological sustenance or institutional isolation, but rather how we might be delivered from meaningless death. The latter requires contextualizing death in a broader vision of human life, or as passage to ultimate destiny beyond life, and through practices of ministering to the dying in a community of care. In this respect, the traditions of religious discourse witness to a conviction that death is not the overriding power that governs our lives, but is itself subject to powers that are ultimate and supreme. The nature and purpose of life, and the place of health, medicine, suffering, and death within a vision of human nature and destiny, while integral to religious discourse, are common human questions of meaning that often seem peripheral in the quandary,centered concerns of bioethics. A central contribution of religious traditions may therefore be to broaden our moral vision by raising issues of existential interest that are not typically addressed in contemporary bioethics. Precisely because these are human questions, they require examination, lest our assumptions about pluralism and ethics consequently compartmentalize our moral lives. Priests and Prophets We value bioethics in a pluralistic moral culture in part because of its capacities for peaceably resolving moral conflict at)out difficult practical dilemmas and hard cases. The success of bioethics in problem-solving is displayed in its increasing institutionalization in health care through the establishment of hospital ethics committees, ethics consultation groups, institutional review boards, and advisory commissions at state and national levels. In these various forums, bioethics discourse is prominently shaped by an ethic of principles--autonomy, beneficence, and justice--that seems well-suited as a method of conflict resolution because such norms are deemed to command general acceptance. In managing and regulating the moral issues that arise in the delivery of health care, bioethics provides an important service for patients, their families, and clinical practitioners. Yet, while this "priestly" role (as it might be viewed in a religious perspective) is a necessary dimension of bioethics, it is not sufficient, for bioethics should be not only a source of solutions but also a source of problems. Part of the responsibility of bioethics is to be "prophetic," challenging to accountability the institutional and professional presuppositions of the health care system and the society of which it is a part. No ethics committee can resolve the scandal of 31.5 million medically indigent persons in this country who may not have access to any institution to begin with. The prophetic responsibility of bioethics necessarily entails probing beneath the visible manifestations of the crisis to identify the root causes of the problem and articulating an alternative vision of the health care system based on ideals of justice in community that may be only approximated in practice. Religious traditions can enhance recognition and implementation of this responsibility, for it is the indicting message of the biblical traditions of this culture that the poor are not to be excluded from the community of moral concern. Moreover, religious traditions can, in several respects, be significant for reminding us of the lira;rations of an ethic of principles. The normative principles of bioethics are not, for example, self-applying or self-interpreting, but instead require a context of application and a content informed by moral traditions--professional, secular, and religious. In this dialogue among traditions, religious discourse can illuminate and acknowledge the validity of a moral principle, even while challenging its conceptual presuppositions. For example, central convictions of theological anthropology in biblical traditions, such as that human beings are created in the image of God, support the notion of intrinsic human dignity and respect for personal choice conveyed in bioethics discourse by the principle of autonomy. Yet such a principle will always appear theologically limited to the extent that its conceptual assumptions reflect an isolated individual severed from community and history. The scope of autonomous choices may be limited by the relational and narrative nature of the self, whose moral identity and character are forged in process of a temporal journey rather than in discrete instances of dramatic decisionmaking. It would, moreover, be theologically narrow to focus on the moral self as a "decisionmaker" or "chooser." Human beings are more than the aggregate of their choices; the "person" whom one respects is an embodied self and the correlative attitude of "respect" must be holistic, acknowledging the moral significance of the bodily organism as well as concerns about liberty of action and freely willed decisions. The self is more than one's capacities for rational, cognitive activity just as the body is more than personal property. In addition, it may be misleading to understand autonomy as a moral ideal for human beings, since freedom of choice may be seriously compromised not only by illness, but also by what biblical traditions have typically designated as "sin," a condition that even Kant believed was so common and radical as to compromise the very conditions for autonomous choice. An assessment of beneficence and justice can evoke similar kinds of overlap and critique. Beneficence. conveys a sense of moral obligation and responsibility for the welfare of others, but its content and scope may seem minimalistic placed alongside norms of love of neighbor Moral philosophers have often maintained that, beyond the fundamental requirement not to harm others, positive actions on behalf of the welfare of other persons are frequently discretionary, as suggested by the language of "imperfect duties" or "supererogation," or mediated by professional roles, such as those assumed by health care practitioners. The substantive requirements of love of neighbor, however, will often demand exceeding minimal or role responsibilities. The themes of self-sacrifice, assuming personal inconvenience and risk, and active seeking of the welfare of others beyond one's conventional community of concern, as displayed paradigmatically in the Christian narrative of the Good Samaritan, may entail that the discretionary takes on the character of the obligatory. The sense that health care is a special kind of good has been an important conceptual underpinning for egalitarian schemes of allocating health care resources. This approach can be supported by the anthropology of the image of God, but it also may be qualified by a historically informed conception of preferential justice towards the poor, the oppressed, and the stranger. Justice may thus require more than a self-interested egalitarianism, namely, a commitment to give special priority to the health care needs of people and groups who have historically experienced oppression and marginalization in our culture. The preferential qualification of egalitarian justice reflects an attempt to redness inequalities stemming from natural and social "givens" with particular attention to the most vulnerable and voiceless in our society. While religious traditions can point to the questions that need to be asked about the meaning and application of a moral principle, they can also inform judgments about what an ethic of principles neglects. For example, such an ethic assumes a sociology of strangers who share little in the way of common values and ends, and there are instances in medicine where such a situation obtains. It would be a mistake, however, to encompass all human relations, and thereby all human choices, under such a model. A richer sense of special moral relationships, embodied in families, friendships, congregations, or in professional collegiality, can attest to the moral significance religious traditions have historically placed on themes of community and covenant. Nor do the normative principles of bioethics, to the extent that they focus our moral vision on questions of what should be done in a situation, give sufficient attention to the issue of what kind of people moral agents should be, or what kinds of virtues are necessary to sustain us in our temporal journey beyond the moment of decisionmaking. The moral teachings of religious traditions speak to matters of meekness, mercy, and purity; knowledge, temperance, and patience; gratitude, courage, and kindness; faith, hope, and love; issues of moral character and identity beyond the scope of decision-oriented principles. A comprehensive bioethics may find in religious discourse about virtues and dispositions an important source of moral correction and balance, one that places our decisions about health care within the context of a fuller account of purpose and meaning in life. Acknowledgments I wish to thank several persons who gave me helpful criticism and needed encouragement, particularly my colleagues at The Hastings Center, Daniel Callahan, Kathleen Nolan, Susan Wolf, and Michael Zeik, all of whom read prior versions of this article; Rabbi Marc Gellman, Ronald Green, Stephen Lammers, Richard Neuhaus, Philip Turner, and Alan Weisbard, who participated in a project meeting on Religion and Bioethics where another version of this article was discussed; and James F. Childress at the University of Virginia. References (n1) H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., "Looking for God and Finding the Abyss Bioethics and Natural Theology," in Theology and Bioethics Exploring the Foundations and Frontiers, Earl E. Shelp, ed. (Boston D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1985), 88. (n2) Leon R. Kass, "Practicing Ethics Where's the Action?," Hastings Center Report 201 (January/February 1990), 6-7. (n3) Stanley Hauerwas, "The Testament of Friends," The Christian Century 1077 (February 28, 1990), 213. (n4) President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Splicing Life (Washington, D.C. U.S. Government Printing Office, 1982), 54. (n5) For a more detailed account of this issue, see Kent Greenawalt, Religious Convictions and Political Choice (New York Oxford University Press, 1988). (n6) Peter Singer, Animal Liberation A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals (New York Random House, Inc., 1975), 21. (n7) H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., "Fashioning an Ethic for Life and Death in a Post-Modern Society," Hastings Center Report 191 (January/February 1989), Special Supplement, 8. (n8) Leon R. Kass, "Averting One's Eyes, or Facing the Music?-On Dignity in Death," Hastings Center Studies 22 (May 1974), 69. (n9) Albert Camus, The Plague (New York Vintage Books, 1948), 121. ~~~~~~~~ by Courtney S. Campbell Courtney S. Campbell is associate for religious studies at The Hastings Center and editor of the Hastings Center Report. -------------------